Omer Bartov:
Industrial Killing: World War I, the Holocaust, and
Representation
Delivered as a lecture at Millersville University,
PA, on April 13, 1997. © Omer Bartov, 1997
http://www.anti-rev.org/textes/Bartov97a/
Nous remercions le professeur Omer Bartov de nous avoir
autorisés à reproduire ce texte.
We are grateful to Professor Omer Bartov for allowing us to make
this text available here.
Today I would like to present to you some of the major themes of
my recently published book, Murder in Our Midst: The Holocaust,
Industrial Killing, and Representation [Oxford University Press,
1996. ISBN: 019509848X].
The book is written in the form of eight interrelated essays
which can also be read independently of each other. It sets out
examine and analyze two main theses, as well as to sketch some
important links between them. First, it argues for a crucial and
largely neglected connection between the Great War of 1914-18 and
the Nazi attempted genocide of the Jews. Second, it asserts the
existence of a complex relationship between the representation and
the enactment of war and genocide in the interwar and postwar
periods.
Both theses are based on the argument that the First World War
had introduced to the West a wholly new concept of war, which in
turn had far-reaching consequences for the understanding of human
society and man's ability to control violence and improve humanity
-- or at least those parts of humanity deemed valuable. This is what
I have termed "industrial killing," namely the mechanized,
impersonal, and sustained mass destruction of human beings,
organized and administered by states, legitimized and set into
motion by scientists and jurists, sanctioned and popularized by
academics and intellectuals. To be sure, there were some precedents
to industrial warfare before the Great War, and the concept of total
war was aired in some quarters prior to 1914. Yet I argue that it
was first and foremost the mass slaughter in the trenches which had
a direct and long-lasting effect on Europe -- and subsequently on
much of the rest of the world -- and that therefore the Great War is
crucial to our understanding of many of the characteristics of
modern war and genocide as well as their popular perception and
representation.
In the first part of the book, "Images of War and the Emergence
of Industrial Killing," I am concerned with the effects of the clash
between the widespread perceptions and anticipations of war in
pre-World War I European society and the realities of modern warfare
confronted in 1914. It was this adaptation of image to reality which
in turn gave birth to a new conceptualization of war and
re-articulated the relationship between violence and modern man, war
and human society. The first two chapters of the book take up
certain aspects of the links between the trauma of war and the new
destructive urge of European society, between fear of personal and
collective annihilation and the evolution of a genocidal mentality,
all within the context of this new and devastating event of
industrial killing.
One important and deeply ironic aspect of this development was
that in the process of attempting to salvage the individual, at
least as a concept if not as a specific entity, from the
annihilating reality of modern warfare, a new concept of total
extermination was forged. War has always created a tension between
its representation as an arena in which the individual warrior could
display his heroic qualities and its reality of anonymous slaughter
where the individual counted for very little. Yet notions of
individual heroism and soldierly chivalry persisted in Europe well
into the twentieth century. The Great War seemed to totally shatter
any illusions regarding individual worth and heroism. Indeed, as the
soldiers soon discovered, precisely those actions deemed heroic, and
therefore meaningful, which could have provided the warrior with a
sense of his own significance, had become both suicidal and
counter-productive in the trenches of the Western Front. While the
old aristocratic or aristocratically-minded officer corps of
European armies was decimated in the first few months of the
fighting, the rank and file found themselves confronted with the
anonymous forces of modern industrial warfare against whose immense
destructive energies they were neither mentally nor materially
prepared. Indeed, much of this century's understanding of modernity
has been molded by the experience of the industrial killing of the
Western Front, which had injected into the progressive, positivist
ideals of the nineteenth-century another layer of meaning (or
meaninglessness), that of modern society's seemingly unlimited and
irrational destructive potential.
The predicament of the individual soldier on the modern
battlefield, I argue, was confronted both on the technical,
practical level, by inventing and producing new technologies which
freed the armies from the fate of being pinned down by the
combination of trenches, barbed-wire, machine guns and artillery,
and on the representational level, by forging a new ideology and
producing a new imagery of heroism and liberation. In the course of
the First World War, and throughout the interwar period, the
inevitability of a perpetual cycle of industrial killing on an ever
greater scale in the future was accepted by all but a small minority
of Europeans. The question became, then, not how to prevent a
repetition of this phenomenon, but how to master it both militarily
and psychologically. In its most extreme form, what emerged was a
radical concept of industrial killing, according to which the only
way to prevent the annihilation of the individual and the collective
to which he belonged was to further perfect the techniques of
killing and to more strenuously mold the mind of the individual so
as to accomplish the total extermination of the enemy. Since the
total war of 1914-18 had already involved much of the nation,
including its non-combatant population, the only way to prevent
similar destruction in the future was therefore to bring about the
total annihilation of those perceived as the nation's enemies, and
thereby to assure one's unchallenged control over the means of
destruction and domination. Hence the notion of industrial killing
was expanded to include what I term "militarized genocide," that is,
the extermination of whole populations as part of a new
conceptualization of modern war.
It is therefore, I argue, not only impossible to understand the
implementation of the "Final Solution" without the context of the
Second World War in which it was perpetrated; it is also crucial to
understand that the manner in which the Second World War was
conducted and the genocidal energies which it unleashed were
themselves part of a larger context of a Europe still coming to
terms with the trauma of the Great War, the first truly industrial
military confrontation in history and the site of industrial killing
of millions of soldiers. This is of course the case as far as
individual perpetrators are concerned, as well as in terms of the
techniques and concepts employed in the death camps. But it is also
important to understand that the preoccupation of Europeans with war
and violence during the interwar period, and the representation of
industrial, rational, yet meaningless killing in art, fiction, and
film, greatly contributed to the articulation of the concept of mass
extermination of whole populations and went a long way to mentally
prepare the perpetrators and bystanders for its actual enactment .
It should be noted that the omnipresence of war in the European
imagination of the interwar period spanned all political and
ideological sectors. Moreover, even those works of fiction and film,
art and rhetoric, which were accepted at the time and are largely
still seen as professing antiwar sentiments were in fact highly
ambivalent, expressing a mixture of disgust and fascination, anger
and admiration, rejection and adulation of war and its makers,
especially the simple soldiers, the most direct victims of their own
actions. In examining, for instance, the works of Henri Barbusse and
Erich Maria Remarque, side by side with those of Louis-Ferdinand
Celine and Ernst Juenger, we are faced with some of the
contradictory reactions to this wholly new experience of industrial
killing. Thus the pacifist Barbusse strives to find a meaning in the
slaughter by presenting it as the dawn of the liberation of the
masses, while the antimilitarist Remarque is imbued with the notion
of comradeship that was so much part of the myth of the
Frontgemeinschaft of the extremist Freikorps and the Nazis.
Conversely, as late as 1932 the future collaborationist,
anti-Semitic, and pro-Nazi Celine portrayed the Great War as an
event of insane mutual slaughter lacking any meaning or
significance, symbolizing to his mind the total worthlessness of
humanity. Juenger, for his part, despite the fact that his writings
provided so much of the imagery of Fascism, described the war as an
intensely personal experience and was much less interested in
attributing to it any universal meaning.
The ambivalent reactions to the cataclysm of the Great War, the
perceived need to endow it with personal, collective, or ideological
meaning, and the desire to integrate the slaughter into a
comprehensible scheme of universal or individual progress, is at the
root of our century's obsession with perpetrating and representing
violence. This can be seen also in much of the cinematic universe of
the interwar period, which was imbued with images of destruction.
Indeed, the films of the 1920s and 1930s very much set the pattern
-- which is still with us today -- of combining revulsion from
violence with highly aestheticized images of destruction, wrath at
the meaninglessness of war and fascination with its perceived
essence and all that it brings out in humanity. This is the case,
for instance, of Jean Renoir and Abel Gance, just as it is of
Georg-Wilhelm Pabst and Fritz Lang, as well as of Lewis Milestone's
cinematic rendering of Remarque's All Quiet on the Western Front.
What is striking about Renoir's The Grand Illusion and The
Rules of the Game, for instance, is that while they condemn the
last war, they are even more critical of post-1918 society, as is
indeed very much Abel Gance's J'accuse in both its somewhat
different versions of 1918 and 1937. Here the soldiers are both the
heroes and the victims, while civilian society both during and after
the war is the true culprit, set on unleashing another war which
only the soldiers know must be an even greater massacre. The
soldiers do not want another war, yet it is only in war that they
know true comradeship and devotion, sacrifice and meaning. Indeed,
it was, in a sense, only in the trenches that they had really lived,
so much so that at a time of emergency they threaten to rise again
and to wipe off the face of the earth all the evil of the postwar
world, as they do in J'accuse and are called upon to do in
Le feu. The world of the trenches had exposed the true meaning
of life, while the postwar world is so filled with hypocrisy and
greed that it takes on the appearance of a soap opera, of foam and
bubbles that can be erased with one swipe of the hand, as it is
portrayed in The Rules of the Game. The illusion was not only
that the war would be fought over a field of flowers, but that the
postwar world would be just and peaceful. The chivalrous
protagonists of The Grand Illusion die, while the new,
ruthless survivors of the war, those who know no rules but those of
the beast, forge the wretched fate of the interwar period.
Nor can there be any hope in technological progress. While in
Pabst's Westfront 1918 the German soldier is finally crushed
into pulp by the advancing tanks of the enemy, in Lang's
Metropolis the machine threatens to take over humanity.
Indeed, Lang's ambivalence about progress and humanity is a
particularly good instance of the dark forebodings and deep
anxieties of his period. The evil forces lurking in the shadows, so
powerfully represented by the child molester and assassin in the
film M, are conquered through an unlikely coalition of the
underworld and the forces of order, the blind (or war mutilated?)
and the children. Yet in the face of this alliance, the killer
suddenly appears as a victim, a helpless pawn at the mercy of a
vindictive world and his own uncontrollable passions. This is a
world turned upside down, where the boundaries between perpetrator
and victim, innocence and guilt, have been shattered, and the
immense power of the mobilized bureaucratic state can be used to any
end, good or evil, or break out of its controls completely, lashing
out at all and sundry with no apparent purpose. This type of
cinematic world is suspended between one apocalypse and another,
seemingly transfixed by such images as Milestone's devastating
machine-gun burst mowing down scores of men on an open field, the
spectators both speechless with horror and fascinated by the
superhuman power of the machine as it wipes out humanity at the
touch of a finger.
The interwar period abounded with memories and anticipations of a
modern, man-made apocalypse, whether in Kafka's In der
Strafkolonie, Franz Werfel's Die vierzig Tage des Musa Dagh,
Hugo Bettauer's Die Stadt ohne Juden, Karl Kraus' Die
letzten Tage der Menschheit, or Kurt Pinthus'
Menschheitsdaemmerung; in the drawing and paintings of Otto Dix
and George Grosz, the war memoirs of Roland Dorgelès and Siegfried
Sassoon, the works and manifestos of the Dadaïsts and the Futurists.
What I would like to stress here is that by the time Europe had
become embroiled in yet another world war, it had already created an
image of military confrontation as an act of total destruction,
frightening and cleansing at the same time, terrifying and yet
fascinating and altogether unavoidable. It is with this context in
mind that I would like to turn to the second part of my book, which
attempts to examine some of the central themes in the histories,
memories, and stories of the Holocaust.
The close links between the interpretations of Antisemitism, the
Holocaust, and National Socialism, clearly reveal their
historiographical interdependence. At the same time, however, the
radically different experiences of writers on these issues and of
their chosen historical protagonists make for the extraordinary
divergences in representations of the relationship between
prejudice, genocide, and Nazism. This can clearly be seen, for
instance, in the different names given to the Holocaust in Germany,
France, the United States, and Israel. The meanings and implications
of calling the event Judenvernichtung or genocide,
Holocaust or Shoah (or Churban or Pur'anut),
should call our attention to the need to investigate the manner in
which Auschwitz (or its repression) has molded different national,
collective, scholarly and literary representations of the past.
A case in point is that of German history writing on the Nazi
period. A good example of the difficulties involved is Andreas
Hillgruber's 1986 book Zweierlei Untergang: Die Zerschlagung des
Deutschen Reiches und das Ende des europaeischen Judentums
(Double Downfall: The Destruction of the German Reich and the End of
European Jewry). There can be little doubt that the two essays
included in this thin volume provide ample proof of the inherent
tension between empathy and detachment, personal experience and
professional identity, politics and scholarship. Thus Hillgruber's
text reflects both his perceived need to historicize the past and
identify with his protagonists -- as befits any self-conscious
Rankean -- and his own wartime experience and exposure to the Nazi
rhetoric of the time. Comparing the first essay (on Germany's
"destruction") to the second (on the "end" of European Jewry), we
can see far more clearly than Hillgruber himself had probably
intended that his stress on the historian's need for empathy with
his protagonists extends only to his own identity-group, and becomes
completely blocked when discussing any other group, especially if it
happens to be composed the former group's victims. This tendency for
powerful but selective empathy has, in turn, some interesting
implications for other German representations of their past, as will
be shown later on.
Some recent works and polemics on the history and memory of the
Holocaust reveal the immense difficulty of studying this event.
Note, for instance, such recent studies as Christopher Browning's
analyses of the bureaucracy, administration, and perpetrators of
genocide, Raul Hilberg's and Gordon Horwitz's works on the
interaction between victims, murderers, and bystanders, and the
essays by Pierre Vidal-Naquet, Alain Finkielkraut, and Lawrence
Langer on the crucial role of memory, its repression, and its abuse.
When examined side by side, these historical investigations and
ruminations seem to suggest that the farther we move away from the
event in time, the more important will it become for subsequent
studies of the Holocaust to take into account all available forms of
representation, and to remain sensitive to the manner in which they
mold both the scholar's and the public's image of the Holocaust, as
well as more generally of genocide as an inherent phenomenon of our
civilization. And yet, while such works enhance our knowledge of
specific areas of the Holocaust, their ultimate effect is profoundly
troubling. This is because they do not leave us with a sense of
greater understanding of the whole; indeed, the profoundly painful
"ruins of memory" manifested by survivors in Langer's work remind us
that neither we, nor indeed the survivors themselves, can
"understand," and that this incomprehension is in many important
ways hereditary, passing from one generation to another as a
recollection of a horror that could not, and can not be exorcized.
Hence Verstehen, the ultimate goal of Einfuehlung, cannot be
achieved, thereby nullifying the very concept of historicization as
far as the victims are concerned. This is all the more disturbing
since these works also indicate that our objective, conscious
reality has simultaneously by and large retained the very same
institutional and psychological structures, biases, and capabilities
which had initially produced the Holocaust. In this case, at least,
knowledge does not produce power, but rather its exact opposite, a
profound sense of powerlessness and anxiety, precisely those
emotions which were so crucial to the perpetration of the act in the
first place.
This brings us to the intellectual debate on the nationalization
and institutionalization of the Holocaust and its commemoration, and
to the implications of historical relativism for the historiography,
representation, and denial of the Nazi genocide. It should be noted
that despite the assertions recently made by such scholars as Arno
Mayer and Charles Maier, in the United States the Holocaust (and its
memory) is the domain of a relatively limited, though not
uninfluential minority and the intellectual/scholarly elite of which
it constitutes an important part. The American public, however, is
generally ignorant about the Holocaust, and is willing to accept its
representation only because it is employed as an example of both the
need for tolerance in a society highly exposed to violence and as a
manifestation of the superiority of American democracy and values,
at a time when American society is undergoing a profound crisis of
confidence. In Israel and Germany, on the other hand, the Holocaust
is a fundamental component of postwar, post-Auschwitz identity, not
least because history as such plays a prominent role in these two
nations' self-perception and politics, quite unlike the case of the
United States, where history is popularly evoked as an adjective for
whatever has become irrelevant. To be sure, the differences between
German and Israeli "coming to terms" with or "reworking" the past
are at least as revealing as the similarities. Moreover,
intellectual influences from both the United States and France have
introduced new elements into the debate which have been taken up by
several interested parties, not always to the benefit of clarity or
understanding. Here I refer first to the bizarre relationship
between American relativists, best represented by Hayden White and
his followers, and German relativization, represented at its most
sophisticated level by Martin Broszat, and more recently by younger
scholars such as Rainer Zitelmann, Goetz Aly, Susanne Heim, and,
somewhat differently, Detlev Peukert. And second, to the links
between the (partly French-influenced) denial of historical truth
and "objectivity," as represented by some poststructuralist and
cultural historians, on the one hand, and the outright denial of the
actual event of the Holocaust, on the other. This debate is
especially pertinent in view of the fact that it was at least partly
anticipated by some writers who had themselves experienced
Auschwitz. By juxtaposing the arguments of relativity with the
accounts and ruminations of such survivors as Primo Levi and Jean
Amery, we may gain more insight, however painful, into their growing
awareness of the ephemerality of personal memory and the pressures
to deny its veracity, which had so greatly informed their thoughts,
anxieties, and ultimate despair.
If the Nazi attempted genocide of the Jews cannot be understood
outside the historical context of the enactment and representation
of industrial killing since 1914, then by the same token the
post-1945 reality and representation of war, violence, and genocide
must be seen within the context of a civilization which had produced
Auschwitz and for which the genocidal enterprise of the Nazis has
become both a measuring-rod and an apology, a terrible warning and a
necessary absence.
In the third and last part of the book I therefore try to look at
the way in which postwar representations of war and genocide,
especially in historiography, fiction, film, and museums, have tried
to confront, or have avoided confronting, the question of evil and
the inherent structures of modern society which had produced
industrial killing. I begin by examining the strong predilection
toward what I term a representation of absence in postwar Germany.
This is to be seen as distinct from the more commonly recognized
absence of representation, which in this case simply denotes
eschewing representations of the victims of the Germans, that is
especially the Jews. What I have in mind here is rather the manner
in which the conscious absence of Jewish victims comes to play a
major role in assuming the status of victims by German protagonists,
both in literary, cinematic, and scholarly representations of the
Nazi period. This can be seen, for instance, in Alexander Kluge's
1979 film The Patriot, which I discuss at some length, as
well as in many other cinematic representations of the German past
made in the 1970s and 1980s, such as Hans-Juergen Syberberg's Hitler, a Film from Germany, Edgar Reitz's
Heimat,
Rainer-Werner Fassbinder's The Marriage of Maria Braun and Lili
Marleen, Helma Sanders-Brahms' Germany, Pale Mother, and others.
Similarly, the German protagonists of such works of fiction as
Heinrich Boell's The Train Came on Time, Guenter Grass' The Tin
Drum, and Siegfried Lenz's The German Lesson, have precisely those
strange and extraordinary characteristics which were at the time
attributed to Jews. In other words, while these protagonists stand
out as the true victims of Nazi society, they simultaneously remain
an inherent part of it, whereas the Jews, who had lost this status
under Nazism, still fail to regain it even in its subsequent German
representations. Examples for this phenomenon of absence of
representation and representation of absence can be found also in
precisely those German works of scholarship which deal with the
Third Reich, or even, indeed, with the Holocaust itself. We may
note, for instance, that Hans Mommsen's "functionalist"
interpretation of the Holocaust is characterized by a distinct
absence of representation, in that the Jews in it are merely the
objects of the process with which he is concerned, and are therefore
of absolutely no interest to him as victims per se, that is, as
objects of either detached investigation or empathy. Conversely,
Martin Broszat's work on everyday life in the Third Reich is, along
with the studies of his numerous disciples, an exercise in
representation of absence par excellence, since it is based on the
perceived need of the historian to empathize with his or her
protagonists while acknowledging that those most deserving of
empathy, namely the obvious victims of the regime, cannot be
accorded it. Hence while German historians must create for
themselves objects of empathy in order to do justice to the
perceived requirements of their profession, both their national
identity and their personal sensibilities preclude the Jews from
serving this purpose.
Moreover, since the most obvious, not to say "natural"
alternative is those historians' own compatriots, we find that
empathy is paradoxically given in disproportionate amounts to the
victimizer and bystander, precisely because they must displace those
who on another level are known to be its strongest claimants. The
examples mentioned above have to do with attempts by those
associated with the perpetrators not merely to repress the memory of
past genocide but also to reformulate the notion of victimhood in a
manner which would integrate perpetrators and victims into one
category of victimhood, as the objects of malign but faceless forces
of fate and history. The difficulties faced by the producers of
German representations of the past are indeed enormous, since
empathy is constantly being displaced and the knowledge of past
crimes is constantly threatening to undermine any attempt at
aestheticizing it by means of conventional artistic, literary, or
scholarly tools. Conversely, attempts to represent war and genocide
in this century by the victims, the bystanders, or those who
perceive themselves to have served a just cause (which the Germans
by and large do not), face a series of problems related to the
nature of postwar modern society in general and, more specifically,
the challenges with which each nation, tradition, or artist is faced
when attempting to script a representational narrative of victimhood
and slaughter and perforce to endow it with some larger meaning.
In the time I have left, I would like briefly to summarize the
closing sections of my book, in which I discuss some of the problems
involved in plastic representations of the Holocaust, and their
implications for the manner in which we understand both the past and
the contemporary nature of our own modern societies. I will discuss Yad Vashem in Jerusalem, the United States Holocaust Memorial Museum
in Washington, D.C., and the Simon Wiesenthal Center's Beit Hashoah
Museum of Tolerance in Los Angeles.
As a national institution, Yad Vashem was set up to serve several
and often contradictory purposes. It is predicated on the assumption
that only the Jewish state can appropriate the memory of the
Holocaust and employ it as part of its own self-definition and
legitimation. Israel is presented as both the consequence and the
panacea: had it existed before the Holocaust, genocide would have
been prevented; and since genocide did occur, there must be a state.
Yet since the Holocaust "belongs" to the state, the victims are
potential Israelis, and the Israelis potential victims. Hence the
historical link is projected into the future, and Israelis are
perceived as survivors of a catastrophe still living on the brink of
an abyss. If Zionism claimed to metamorphose the Jews of the
Diaspora into a new breed, Yad Vashem makes them into the direct
offspring of the murdered, avengers of their blood and preservers of
their memory. The significance of Yad Vashem is derived first and
foremost from its location. Yet the Holocaust occurred elsewhere:
the camps are scattered throughout Central and Eastern Europe.
Ancient rulers used to put up columns on the sites of their
victories. But the Holocaust was humanity's greatest defeat. Can
this devastating debacle at the end of what we like to think of as
millennia of progress be commemorated where it happened? Or should
it be remembered where the tortuous journey to Auschwitz began?
Alternatively, can the Holocaust be made part of the New World,
integrated into the fabric of American aspirations and optimism, not
in order to qualify them, but to be qualified itself, as a terrible,
but by no means fatal road accident on the highway to a better
future? If the overt function of Yad Vashem is to prove the need for
a Jewish state, not merely to document its tragic legacy, the
ambiguity of the event's "lessons" is nevertheless evident in the
uncertainty of its rhetoric. Although it gives great prominence to
the Warsaw Ghetto rebellion, and tries to assert that the "natural"
culmination of the Holocaust was the establishment of Israel, the
very nature of the event, once exhibited, defeats this purpose, and
one does not come away from the museum with a sense of triumph, nor
with a feeling that this reordering of the past has liberated its
future, our present, of ambiguity and doubt.
Such contradictions are also characteristic of the Holocaust
Museum in Washington, located as it is in the capital of a nation
most of whose population was neither directly nor indirectly touched
by the event. This site has the potential of universalizing the
Holocaust as a phenomenon of major significance for human
civilization as a whole. Yet universalizing the Holocaust may either
mean that it "belongs" to all of humanity, or merely imply a shared
responsibility; it may assert that genocide is a perpetual potential
of human civilization, or that the Holocaust was merely one of
innumerable mass murders in history. The museum may be intended to
commemorate and remember the historical event of the Holocaust, or
to employ it as a symbol of persecution and mass murder. Moreover,
if the museum presents the Jews as the victims, is America the
savior? And what about all other ethnic and cultural minorities in
American society? Indeed, if modern civilization is the context,
where does the United States fit in?
Like all cultural institutions, the Holocaust Memorial Museum is
not only about memory and its commemoration: it is about the
relationship between the politics of the present and interpretations
of the past. But for many visitors, the museum represents what the
past was actually like. Having been "there," we think we know,
because we saw and felt it. And on the basis of that "knowledge" we
also reevaluate, or reconfirm, our perceptions of our own society,
of ourselves. Are we comfortable with the stark differences between
here and there, then and now, and do we want to maintain them, at
least in our minds, or can we perceive the potential similarities?
Beyond the walls of the museum we know the zones of plenty and
power, danger and poverty, racism and violence. But we also know
that this is not as bad as that. Does the museum, then, have a
galvanizing or a debilitating effect? Does it subvert or legitimize?
Does it not accuse those who can no longer be punished and acquit
those who are still among us, even ourselves?
The self-legitimizing effect of the museum is also part of its
exhibit, which devotes little space to the role of science and the
legal profession in sanctioning and promoting the murder of
undesirable human beings. The Holocaust in this museum is a German
affair, its victims are mostly Jews, and the perpetrators are mainly
identifiable Nazis. In this sense, we are provided with a strangely
comforting narrative, since Germany has been evidently transformed,
the Nazis are presumably no longer with us, and Antisemitism is
supposedly restricted now to a few marginal fanatics. The Holocaust,
then, keeps happening only within the confines of the museum, and
we, the visitors, are safe from its implications by the very fact
that we can only see it exhibited as an historical event.
And yet, as I have argued before, the genocide of the Jews was
not only a perfection and extension of the industrial killing of
World War I, but also an enterprise that could have been
accomplished only by a highly modern, disciplined, bureaucratic
society, in which people had respect for law and order, science and
technology, that is, a society very much like the Western
industrialized states in which we now live. Indeed, if there is any
lesson to be drawn from the Holocaust, it is that unlike numerous
previous and subsequent genocides, the crucial precondition for this
kind of industrial murder is the modern, industrialized,
bureaucratic state. Yet it is unlikely that such a state would allow
the erection of a major cultural institution whose narrative would
threaten to subvert its very identity.
For its part, the Simon Wisenthal Center's Beit Hashoah Museum of
Tolerance in Los Angeles accepts the relevance of the Holocaust for
contemporary conditions, and yet frames its meaning for the present
within an opaque narrative of tolerance. Since prejudice was at the
root of genocide, all that is needed is a change of heart; not a
transformation of the conditions which perpetuate frustration and
violence, but a different perception.
It is precisely this which the Museum of Tolerance tries to
achieve. Assuming that its visitors are incapable of comprehending
complex verbal or written messages, it provides them with a heavy
dose of emotionally laden images, slogans and crude simplifications.
The visitor is urged to "feel" the events plastically displayed,
while being simultaneously warned of evil manipulators of public
opinion and emotion such as Hitler and Stalin. If genocide was made
possible by evil leaders, fanaticized followers, and indifferent
masses, our own responsibility is to feel the injustice and
inhumanity of those regimes and oppose them with our own purer
emotions.
The effect of this message of tolerance is similar to television,
producing an emotional reaction yet encouraging passivity. For what
is the political agenda of tolerance? Should everyone be tolerated,
or are some people and regimes wholly intolerable? Does empathy for
victims imply action against perpetrators? Or does this version of
tolerance legitimize our acceptance of glaring inequality and
injustice, so long as we learn to love each other? To a striking
degree, this high-tech museum displaces memory and history by means
of an electronically-generated, ahistorically-oriented emotional
catharsis, based on the assumption that such simulated experiences
can be directly translated into so-called "genocide prevention."
This type of education via simulation relies heavily on the senses
and emotions and neglects the intellect. Curiously, this was also a
central trope of fascism, that created vast "emotions factories"
whose goal was to manipulate the masses and annihilate criticism,
attributing cold intellectualism and an inability to empathize to
the real or imaginary enemies of the state. Indeed, while the
"factories of death" were the epitome of bureaucratized genocide,
their own essential precondition was largely the "emotions
factories" that generated the popular support for the regime that
controlled them, and the distorted perceptions of reality that made
complicity in mass murder so widespread.
Thus the Museum of Tolerance can be said to close a vicious
circle of the representation of violence in our century,
notwithstanding its good intentions. Here simulated genocide
converts the event into a mere image which can be "experienced" and
discarded at will. By trying to make the audience "feel" the event,
the museum extracts it from its historical context, negating its
past reality altogether. By making the artifacts more comprehensible
and the exhibit "more real" than the event itself, the whole
spectacle is made ultimately "better," and certainly more "useful"
as a guide for the future, than the reality on which it claims to be
based.
This emphasis on an unreflective emotionality rather than
understanding, this privileging of pathos over knowledge, this
reliance on representing stark oppositions, assumes a mentality in
the public which the museum in fact helps to create and perpetuate.
Moreover, it obscures not only the bureaucratic character of the
Holocaust, but also the fact that while the makers of genocide and
their supporters were themselves driven by images they perceived as
reality, it was science and technology, celebrated in the museum,
which were an inherent part of envisioning and implementing
Auschwitz. Hence the emotions-factories of Nazi propaganda were
essential for the technological factories of death; trying to grasp
this complexity by means of a hyperrealistic exhibit within a
hypertechnological environment seems not merely to make for a
misunderstanding of the past but also for a perpetuation of its
potential future perils.
|