Honest
liberals know that they are not pluralists. They
know that the liberal worldview does not recognize
the validity of other worldviews, and that it
aspires–using all the economic, media, and military
means at its disposal–to make itself dominant.
Liberalism is not tolerance, liberalism is not
pluralism, and admitting this is not a mark against
it; it is simply to recognize the difference between
the perception of a liberal agenda as the just,
indispensable agenda, and “let a thousand flowers
bloom.”
But not all
liberals are willing to admit this. The greatest
teacher of those liberals who are convinced that
they are pluralists was Isaiah Berlin. Berlin’s
thought, more than any other liberal doctrine
formulated in the twentieth century, reveals a
conceptual confusion between pluralism and
liberalism. At the end of the twentieth century,
this confusion did not appear to be critical or
potentially dangerous. In the 1990s, with the fall
of the Eastern Bloc, with the euphoric rise of
capital markets, and with the fashionable
post-modernist discourse that flourished in
academia, the West celebrated what seemed to be its
final victory. For ten years it had no enemies, and
when you have no enemies, it is possible to babble
on about pluralism, denigrate the “oppressive”
culture of the West, and demand that the “voice of
the other should also be heard.” The multicultural
discourse that flourished at the time did not stand
up to scrutiny, because the “other” did not speak.
On September 11, 2001, four years after the death of
Berlin, we heard the clear voice of the “other.”
Since Osama Bin
Laden made his voice heard, every liberal has had to
figure out for himself if he really is a pluralist,
as he imagined himself to be. This is no longer an
academic or theoretical issue. To counter the clear
voices of the enemies of the West, the West must
speak out clearly, or else it will be defeated. This
year, Europe has incurred Muslim riots in France and
Muslim unrest in England and Germany; it has enabled
the “others” to build mosques in its capitals that
nurture hatred of the West. The repercussions of
this foolishness in the name of pluralism were
foreseeable but are still being denied. French
intellectuals were quick to interpret–and
justify–the riots in Paris by portraying them as
acts of protest by the poor and the downtrodden.
They presented the issue as a social struggle, and
in so doing exempted themselves from the question of
pluralism. When the Muslim “other” is portrayed as
oppressed, his true and declared identity as a
jihadist soldier is denied, and so the test facing
multicultural pluralism in our time is rejected.
Understanding Berlin’s philosophical doctrine,
therefore, has become a pressing matter for our
time.
II
In
three respects, Berlin deserves our profound esteem.
The first
relates to his contribution to the discipline known
as “the history of ideas.” Hegel had already been as
much a historian of philosophy as he was a
philosopher of history. But unlike Hegel, Berlin
wrote in a fluent and communicative style that could
hold readers spellbound. He gave us guided tours of
the mid-nineteenth-century Russian scene;1
he rescued from oblivion thinkers such as Joseph de
Maistre and Johann Georg Hamann, and he shed new
light on others, like Machiavelli, Vico, Herder, and
Montesquieu. As distinct from classical political
history or economic-sociological history, he wrote
spiritual-cultural history. Departing from the
ahistorical teaching method practiced in philosophy
departments, he rooted every philosophical doctrine
in the historical context that gave rise to it.
Today, this approach seems obvious, but it became so
thanks to him.
Second, Berlin
revived the debate on the great moral and political
questions in a period when logic was all the rage.
Oxford, where he studied and taught, was then the
capital of analytic philosophy. A serious
philosopher was thought to be a kind of linguistic
surgeon, prohibited from stepping outside the
operating room. That was the philosophical climate
when Berlin was taking his first steps, and at the
beginning of his journey he tried to be accepted by
the club. He wrote several papers on logic, but lost
interest in it towards the middle of the century. In
1950 he was still publishing technical articles with
titles like “Empirical Propositions and Hypothetical
Statements” and “Logical Translation,” but in the
same year he also published “Political Ideas in the
Twentieth Century” and “Socialism and Socialist
Theories,” essays that marked his assault on the
great questions and the wider educated public.2
In his rebellion against Oxford thinking, he became
an oasis in the analytic desert.
Third, Berlin
was a gifted writer. It is a pleasure to read him.
He dictated most of his essays, endowing them with a
narrative, flowing quality. As Michael Ignatieff
said, with Berlin “the way he writes and the way he
talks are identical: Ornate, elaborate,
old-fashioned, yet incisive and clear…. Words come
at his bidding and they form into sentences and
paragraphs as quickly as he can bring them on.”3
That is why Berlin’s sentences are syntactically
long and complex–ready to burst, replete with
attributive clauses that modify every argument. “He
outlines a proposition and anticipates objections
and qualifications as he speaks, so that both
proposition and qualification are spun out in one.”4
His style of presenting his thoughts in flight is a
virtuosic improvisation–a lively voice, not a stiff
one. Few are the writers who have achieved this
quality. Deep scholarship and charismatic writing
hardly ever meet; they meet in his essays.
Yet these achievements, great as they may be, are
irrelevant to an appreciation of Berlin’s
philosophical doctrine. As one who was widely
considered one of the most important political
philosophers of the twentieth century, he demands we
discuss him on his own terms. A philosopher is not
judged by his eloquence; Hegel, as we know, wrote
dreadfully, and no one would say that Leibniz, or
Kant or Husserl, for instance, excelled at writing.
It is the greatness of Berlin as a philosopher, not
as a writer, that needs to be assessed.
Romanticism, nationalism, pluralism: These are
Berlin’s three great subjects. He established his
fame as a commentator on Romanticism, as a liberal
who recognized the importance of nationalism, and as
a philosopher who raised the banner of pluralism.
These are the three basic principles of his
doctrine, and they are intertwined and together form
a triangle at the apex of which is pluralism.
Pluralism was The Topic, the epicenter of his
thinking; the other two served only as a means of
presenting his pluralistic arguments. Of course he
also wrote on other subjects,5
but our interest is not in a review of all his
writings but in an understanding of the essence of
his doctrine.
Berlin divided
the intellectuals who molded Western culture into
monists, whom he nicknamed “hedgehogs,” and
pluralists, whom he dubbed “foxes.” The hedgehogs
are the bad guys, and the foxes the good guys.
Plato, Hegel, and Nietzsche are hedgehogs, whereas
Aristotle, Montaigne, and Goethe are foxes.6
It is irrelevant what each of them professed, or the
theoretical or literary genre in which each
expressed himself–only the general mentality, the
hedgehoginess or the foxiness, so to speak, is
important. From this ethereal perspective, Berlin
dealt with Europe’s ideological history. The
Enlightenment philosophers interested him as
hedgehogs, whereas Machiavelli, the Romanticists,
and the nineteenth-century Russian thinkers
interested him only as foxes. There was no
philosophical, ideological, or cultural stream that
Berlin did not assign to one of the two cages. He
did not acknowledge the existence of other animals.7
The reason for
his fixation was in large part biographical. He grew
up in the shadow of the rise of the totalitarian
regimes–a Jew born in Latvia, he fled the Bolsheviks
at the age of eleven, and thirty years later those
of his relatives who had remained there were
murdered by the Nazis. He belonged, therefore, to
the same generation of refugees (Jews and others) as
Karl Popper, Friedrich Hayek, Vladimir Nabokov,
Hannah Arendt, Max Horkheimer, Theodor Adorno, and
Jacob Talmon, who had first-hand experience of the
totalitarian trauma, and liberals such as Albert
Camus and George Orwell, who watched in horror from
the wings. World War II led to a philosophical and
literary mobilization to expose and uproot
totalitarianism, and Berlin was one of the first to
enlist.
The question
that troubled Berlin, Popper, Talmon, and their like
was this: What is it about the Western way of
thinking that gives rise to totalitarian regimes?
Their working assumption was that these regimes
arose not just as a result of the economic, social,
and political problems that had been created at the
beginning of the twentieth century, but also, and
for the main part, because they encompassed a
totalitarian way of thinking that had been a part of
Western culture for hundreds of years. Talmon
identified the beginning of totalitarianism with the
French Revolution, Horkheimer and Adorno saw its
roots in the Enlightenment, and Popper and Berlin
found its origins as far back as Plato.8
Popper drew a straight line from Plato to Hegel and
from him to Marx–the three greatest enemies of “the
open society”9–and
Berlin filled in this line with many other names
that he felt represented the monistic, dogmatic,
“hedgehog” way of thinking that we must rid
ourselves of lest the totalitarian regimes rise
again from within us.
Even though
Berlin, like Popper, applied his thesis concerning
the roots of totalitarianism to the entire history
of European thought, he focused on one specific
period, which in his opinion was the most important
in the history of the West. Berlin returns to this
period, which rocked Europe around 1800, from
different angles in almost all his essays. From 1960
on, he identified that historical upheaval with “the
Romantic Revolution,” and from 1972 on, he claimed
that the rise of nationalism was also a part of it.
Once his thesis included references to both
Romanticism and nationalism, he gained renown as an
intellectual who demonstrated his pluralism by
describing illiberal ideological movements candidly,
without arrogance or tendentiousness.
But this is a
misimpression, one which stems mainly from Berlin’s
easy-going style. He did not disparage illiberal
writers and currents of thought the way Popper and
Hayek did, but reviewed them with a scholarly,
“objective” detachment. In all his essays, there is
not even one outburst of anger or venom; an Olympian
tone is maintained throughout. In every one of his
essays one has to extract his point of view from the
opinions and cultural associations he pulls out of
his pocket in handfuls, like a kindly old man
feeding pigeons in the city square. Thanks to the
breadth of his horizons, Berlin succeeded in being
portrayed as a fox. In fact, he was a hedgehog par
excellence, a soft-spoken dogmatist.
III
Berlin
blamed the Enlightenment for sowing the seeds of
totalitarian thinking. The arrogance of the
Enlightenment’s enlistment of reason in creating a
perfect, utterly rational world, spawned the tyranny
of Robespierre, and in the twentieth century, the
KGB state. Berlin maintains that the Romantic
movement was born as a justified counter-reaction to
the dogmatic optimism of the Enlightenment. The
Romanticists were, in his view, the first
pluralists. To be a Romanticist was to be a
pluralist.
All the values
and motifs normally attributed to the Romantic
movement seemed to him erroneous or inessential:
Turbulence, violence, conflict, chaos… the strange,
the exotic, the grotesque, the mysterious, the
supernatural, ruins, moonlight, enchanted castles…
darkness and the powers of darkness, phantoms,
vampires, nameless terror, the irrational… Gothic
cathedrals, mists of antiquity… the impalpable, the
imponderable… it is nostalgia, it is reverie, it is
intoxicating dreams, it is sweet melancholy and
bitter melancholy, solitude, the sufferings of
exile, the sense of alienation, roaming in remote
places, especially the East, and in remote times,
especially the Middle Ages… energy, force, will,
life… wild exhibitionism, eccentricity… the damned
soul, the Corsairs, Manfreds, Giaours, Laras, Cains…
Satanic revels, cynical irony, diabolical laughter,
black heroes….
And so forth.10
In Berlin’s opinion, the essence of Romanticism is
not to be found in this nocturnal world. The essence
of Romanticism is for him the revolutionary
discovery that it is impossible to reconcile
conflicting values. “The belief… that somewhere
there exists a solution for every problem… is the
major assumption that is presupposed in the whole of
Western thought up to the point of which I speak,”
ruled Berlin.11
He thought that all the thinkers who preceded the
Romanticists believed that “goals… cannot possibly
conflict with one another.” This is because even if
human values are many and varied, in the end “they
must form a harmonious whole.”12
According to
Berlin, the Romanticists were the first to deny
this, and their revolutionary rejection of
harmonious monism which everyone in Western culture
had believed in and championed until then, was not
only the
turning point in Western history, but also–from the
point of view of an advocate of pluralism–the most
welcome
philosophical discovery in history: “Even the
relativists and the sceptics [from the Greek
Sophists to Montesquieu] said no more than that
individuals and societies had different needs in
accordance with different geographical or climatic
conditions, or different systems of law and
education, or general outlooks and patterns of
life.”13
That is to say, until the coming of the
Romanticists, no adequate account was taken of
possible conflicts between absolute values.
Was this indeed
Romanticism’s innovation? Had there not been
recognition of the insoluble conflict between
absolute values as far back as the fifth century
b.c.e.
in the tragedies of Aeschylus, Sophocles, and
Euripides? A man’s loyalty to his family was
perceived in Greece as an absolute value, as was his
loyalty to his city-state, and therefore there was
no ultimate solution, only a solution of might, to a
situation in which these two values conflicted, as
in Sophocles’ Antigone.14
Creon can destroy Antigone, but he cannot destroy
the validity of her argument. They are both right,
and there is no higher value that can, as with
Hegel, provide a “synthesis.” This is not moral
relativism; the Athenian tragedies were not
concerned with demonstrating the local relativity of
human values (i.e., values are mere customs), but
with the irresoluble conflict between absolute
values.15
“Aeschylus,” writes Nathan Spiegel, “infused tragedy
with a dimension of moral and spiritual complexity–a
complexity that a man encounters whenever his soul
is torn between opposing values each of which is
just and valid.”16
This recognition was passed on from the Athenian
tragedians to Shakespeare, Racine, Milton, and
Dostoevsky.17
Berlin did not
agree. In his view, all the philosophers and writers
who preceded Romanticism thought that “there is
nothing in the nature of men or the world which
makes tragedy unavoidable,” because they all
believed that “sin, crime, suffering are forms of
maladjustment due to blindness.”18
This is a strange claim to say the least, for what
is the tragic worldview if not the perception of
tragedy as inevitable? And what is Greek tragedy if
it does not show us that “sin, crime, suffering” are
the lot of every man, wise and moral as he may be,
since we are all pawns in the hands of blind fate,
and since even in the small domain in which we have
control over our lives, we cannot apply one absolute
moral value without impinging on another? “For the
Greeks,” answered Berlin, “tragedy was error which
the gods sent upon you, which no man subject to them
could perhaps have avoided; but, in principle, if
these men had been omniscient, they would not have
committed those grave errors which they did commit,
and therefore would not have brought misfortunes
upon themselves.”19
Another strange claim, for according to the Greek
view fate rules not just human beings but also the
gods. Not the gods but fate brings down disasters on
human beings, and these disasters are not “errors”
that man or god
can prevent.
Alongside the
Greek culture that believed in a mysterious,
incomprehensible, invisible, and omnipotent fate, a
culture developed in ancient Israel that believed in
a mysterious, incomprehensible, invisible, and
omnipotent God. The Bible endowed Western
civilization with the notion that, to use Berlin’s
words, “your very action expresses–is one with–your
convictions. Morality and politics are not a set of
propositions: They are action, self-dedication to
goals made concrete. To be a man is not to
understand or reason but to act; to act, to make, to
create, to be free are identical: this is the
difference between the animals and man.”20
But Berlin did not
write this about the biblical point of view.
He wrote it about the Romantic point of view.
Did Berlin not
know that the history of his people is the history
of a human collective that said “we will do and
obey,” because it did not make the observance of the
commandments conditional on understanding
them? “Self-dedication to goals made
concrete,” action and not theory, a doctrine that is
all imperatives
(without any philosophical statement)–a
revolutionary discovery indeed, but an ancient one.
Did he not know that the Jewish faith does not
perceive reality as the embodiment of cosmic
intelligence
(as the Egyptians, Chinese and Indians, and
Aristotle and Spinoza knew it to be), but as the
embodiment of God’s will? Or that it therefore
demands that its believers (as Christianity and
Islam later demanded) voluntarily control their
impulses and needs, and live accordingly in God’s
image? And did he not know, when he defined the
Romantic community as a community that “insulates
itself against outside interference in order to be
independent and express its own inner personality,”21
that introverted isolation was his own people’s
policy–“a people that shall dwell alone, and shall
not be reckoned among the nations”–from biblical
times until the present day?
It was not the
Romantics but the Athenian tragedians who taught us
that conflicting values cannot be reconciled; not
the Romantics but the Bible that taught that will is
more important than reason. With the Greek legacy on
the one hand and the Judeo-Christian on the other,
Western culture evolved into one for which
non-rationalism was as natural as oxygen. At no
time, at least until the French Revolution, was the
influence of rationalist philosophers greater than
the influence of popes or local preachers, kings,
despots, troubadours, and groups of traveling
actors, architects of cathedrals and the artists who
painted their murals, witch burners, and persecutors
of Jews–all those rulers, spiritual shepherds,
artists, and other creators of consciousness who
made Europe what it is.
Anyone looking
for a harmonious, rationalist culture will be more
likely to find it in China or India.22
The Chinese and the Indians, not the Europeans,
would agree with Berlin that “sin, crime, suffering
are forms of maladjustment due to blindness,” and
that “there is nothing in the nature of men or the
world which makes tragedy unavoidable.” The concept
of “tragedy” is foreign to the Chinese and the
Indians; the world is perfect and each person can be
just as perfect if he undertakes the necessary study
of Taoism, Confucianism, Hinduism, or Buddhism.
Berlin presented Western culture–restless,
tormented, turbulent, from an Eastern point of
view–as a culture characterized from the very dawn
of its creation and almost throughout its existence
by all-resolving rationalism, until the Romantics
came and introduced Europe to the possibility of
restlessness, torment, and turbulence.
According to Berlin, the Romantic ethos is
“something altogether new in the European
consciousness,” because “what matters now is motive,
integrity, sincerity, fidelity in principle, purity
of heart, spontaneity; not happiness or strength or
wisdom or success, or natural beauty, or other
natural values, which are outside the realm of moral
freedom.” A Romanticist does not care “whether, in a
worldly sense, he succeeds or does not succeed”;
thus he acknowledges that grief, not necessarily
happiness, will descend on him the more he knows
about the world; thus he acknowledges that “justice
may preclude mercy”; and thus he acknowledges that
“if man were not free to choose evil, he would not
be truly free.”23
Yet again, there is not a word here that is not
compatible with either the biblical ethos or
Athenian tragedy.
“The very
concept of idealism as a noble attribute is novel,”
Berlin says, continuing to burst through doors that
were opened 2,500 years ago. “To praise someone as
an idealist is to say that he is prepared to lay
down his life for ends in which he believes for
their own sake [and not for the sake of success or
happiness or any kind of reward].”24
And in order to explain to us why this is not
precisely what the first Christians did (another Jew
in his place would also have recalled all those Jews
who died as martyrs in the last two thousand years),
Berlin says: “It had always been right for a
Christian to die for his faith; but that was because
it was the true faith, and only by it could a man be
saved, and therefore it constituted the highest
value in his scale, and not in his alone, but in
that of all mankind.”25
But when a Romanticist gave up his life he did it
for his personal values, his and only his.26
This is the
crucial error in Berlin’s definition of Romanticism.
Until now he was wrong only in defining the Romantic
ethos as innovative;
now he is mistaken in defining its
essence.
When he talks about “idealism” (whatever that
implies) and about “goals” that the Romanticist sets
for himself (whatever they may be), he empties the
Romantic ethos of its content. It is of no
importance, according to Berlin, what the
Romanticists stood for; all that is important is
that each of them had his own private ideal and
lived for it. “We can give [our values] no reason
save that that is what we aim at, that these are the
goals that are ours because we have chosen them.”27
This is what he calls Romantic “idealism.” It is
possible that this arbitrary “idealism” was typical
of Sartrean existentialism,28
but Romanticism held to a
specific ethos. It sanctified the
night. That was its message.
By day, man is a
social animal. By night, man does not remember that
he is a citizen, has no recollection of his duty, of
his colleagues, not even of his family; at night he
dreams. Savagery, violence, scenes of lechery and
horror, voyages into the magical and descents into
the despicable–it happens to us all, night after
night, and no one thought it worth glorifying until
the advent of the Romantics. We do not have space to
list here all the Romantic poems, from Novalis’
“Hymns to the Night” (1797) to Bialik’s “Secrets of
the Night” (1899), in which the subject of night
appears in their titles.29
All of E.T.A. Hoffmann’s tales are nightmares, and
more indirectly, so are Kleist’s. The demonic,
Gothic, nocturnal darkness cloaks the entire
Romantic world of images. The Romanticists glorified
Cain, Kublai Khan, Don Juan, Napoleon, the genius
sociopath who appears in the world as one of
nature’s terrible forces. The metaphysical idealism
of Fichte and Schopenhauer is profoundly dark and
utterly opposed to Spinoza’s tranquil pantheism and
the Arcadian nature that Rousseau so longed for.30
In every poem by Coleridge, in every painting by
Turner, in every note by Wagner, speaks the Lord of
the Night.
It was not
nihilism but a new ethos. It was not the lack of a
scale of values but the overturning of a scale of
values that denied night and glistened from too much
Enlightenment sunlight. “Enlightenment,” declared
Kant, “is man’s emergence from his self-incurred
immaturity”–and this emergence to maturity is an
emergence from slavery to freedom, to independence.31
Enlightened man is not a slave of superstition or of
impulse, emotion, or other rubbish. His rationality
is his freedom. There is no night in his soul. On
the other hand, the Romanticists maintained that
this “freedom” was slavery; that “reason” was the
trampling of true freedom–the nocturnal freedom to
live and express the deeper, fascinating, exciting,
vital, energetic side of the human soul. What makes
man different from the animals is not that he has
intelligence (what creature does not have some form
of intelligence?) but that man and only man has
imagination. It follows that the artist, the knight
of imagination, and not the philosopher, the knight
of reason, is the exemplary human being, the
Romantic “genius.” Art is the most important human
activity, and of all forms of art, music and poetry
are the most important, because the nocturnal,
ecstatic-demonic potential of music and poetry is
greater than that of any other art form.32
That was the essence of the Romantic revolution: The
idea that art was more important than anything else,
not for expressing shapely “beauty,” but for
expressing the “sublime,” the terrifying, the
nocturnal.33
Berlin attributed a pluralism to Romanticism that
was not there, and did not see what was there. He
was night-blind. It is important to differentiate
between an error derived from a specific shortcoming
in an intellectual’s way of thinking and an error
arising from his agenda. Berlin’s night blindness
derived from his agenda, from which also derived his
error in understanding the second major object of
his attention: National consciousness.
IV
Inasmuch
as Berlin made his name as an interpreter of
Romanticism, he was revered as a liberal who
recognized the significance of nationalism. True, he
recognized its significance as a historical
phenomenon–but who does not
recognize it as such? Serious
recognition of nationalism is admission not just of
its historical importance, but of its ideological
importance.
Berlin was
indeed a Zionist, but as Avishai Margalit remarks,
“Berlin’s Zionism was not an ideology which derives
from primary principles such as nationalism or
liberalism. His Zionism was for him more akin to a
family business than to a doctrine.”34
In other words, Berlin was a Zionist without having
clarified what his philosophical attitude was
towards the question of nationalism. Moreover, his
support for Zionism in fact diverged from his
political philosophy, since this support was not
compatible with his hostility towards other
nationalist movements, as Richard Wollheim notes.35
If he hadn’t been Jewish, he likely would have
opposed Zionism in the same way he had opposed the
other nationalisms.
Nationalism, as
Berlin understood it, is essentially a modern
European phenomenon. The self-esteem of the Germans,
the Italians, the Poles, and the Russians was badly
damaged around 1800 both as a result of the efforts
of rulers like Frederick the Great and Peter the
Great to impose the values and manners of the French
Enlightenment, and to an even greater extent as a
consequence of Napoleon’s military and cultural
conquest. In other words, not only is nationalism
essentially European, but it is merely an
emotional reaction
to humiliation and indignity. It is not a reasoned
political philosophy or worldview–in fact, it is
doubtful if it is at all worthy of the description
“worldview,” since it is purely emotional. It is a
collective convulsion, a reflex, a response to some
excruciating irritation, as one scratches one’s
psoriasis.
Berlin is duly
aware of the difference between chauvinist
nationalism and tolerant national consciousness.
“Nationalism is an inflamed condition of national
consciousness which can be, and has on occasion
been, tolerant and peaceful. It usually seems to be
caused by wounds, some form of collective
humiliation.”36
The reader may well get the impression, therefore,
that Berlin is referring only to chauvinist
nationalism–not peaceful national consciousness–as
an “emotional fever,” and this impression raises the
expectation of a
non-volatile discussion of national
consciousness. For if “national consciousness” does
not mean chauvinism, what kind of ideological
position is it? Our expectation goes unfulfilled.
Berlin has nothing to say about nationalist
ideology; he says only what everyone already knows:
Chauvinism and national consciousness are not the
same thing. One does not know, therefore, what he
means when he writes that “what we are seeing, it
seems to me, is a world reaction against the central
doctrines of nineteenth-century liberal rationalism
itself, a confused effort to return to an older
morality.”37
Chauvinism or national consciousness? The difference
is of no importance, for after all, one way or the
other, he considered them to be nothing more than a
reaction to liberal rationalism–and Berlin, being a
liberal, cannot therefore recognize it as a
political philosophy. It is not a form of reason,
merely a reaction.38
Is nationalism
indeed essentially a modern European (and
reactionary) phenomenon? Is it not actually even
more ancient than the Greek recognition of the
incompatibility of absolute values, which Berlin
portrayed as a discovery of Romanticism?
Nationalism was
born three thousand years ago in ancient Israel.39
For the last two thousand years, by their own
irritating existence as a nation, the Jews acted as
a constant reminder of the national idea for the
people among whom they lived. In fact, the Jews
presented the challenge of nationality to their
hosts as far back as the fourth century
b.c.e.,
if the book of Esther is to be believed. Mordechai
refuses to bow down in front of Haman, the
representative of the Persian Empire, not because he
holds him in personal contempt, but because
Mordechai’s self-definition is national rather than
civic. Haman complains about him to Ahasverus in
these words: “There is a certain people scattered
abroad and dispersed among the people in all the
provinces of thy kingdom; and their laws are
different from all people; nor do they keep the
king’s laws.”40
Haman realized, as all subsequent hosts of the Jews
realized, that the national self-definition of the
Jews does not depend on territorial possessions,
political sovereignty, or a state constitution. The
people of Israel obviously yearned for territory,
sovereignty, and statehood, but it demonstrated to
the European and Arab nations what it demonstrated
to Ahasverus and Haman: That nationhood is a
category in itself and is not derived from other
categories.41
The nationalist
idea is not racist. If we understand the Bible as
the autobiography of the people of Israel, then it
emphasizes at all its key junctures the independence
of the definition of nationhood from the ethnic
origin of the fathers of the nation or the ethnic
background of those who joined it. There is no
Hebrew “race,” and according to the division of
biblical humanity into races (Shem, Ham, and
Japhet), the people of Israel cannot even be said to
belong pure and simple to the Semitic race. Osnat
the Egyptian, Joseph’s wife, Zipporah the
Midianite-Ethiopian, Moses’ wife, Jezebel the
Phoenician, Ahab’s wife, and the many Canaanite
women taken for wives during the Kingdom of Israel,
mixed Semitic blood with the blood of Ham,42
and Solomon’s harem probably included women from the
race of Japhet. Moreover, even if we consider only
the Semitic elements of the people of Israel, the
Bible underscores their heterogeneity: The four
“mothers” were Aramaic; the house of David was the
offspring of Ruth the Moabite.
This ethnic mix
is at the root of the difference between the people
of Israel and other ancient peoples. The biblical
authors created a
nation that is explicitly an artificial
collective identity. Belonging to a people is a
biological fact; belonging to a nation is a
conscious belonging to an “imagined community,” as
Benedict Anderson put it.43
“Imagined”–that is to say, essentially fictional.
According to Ernest Gellner, “Nationalism is not the
awakening of nations to self-consciousness; it
invents nations where they do not exist.”44
On an ethno-biological level, the land of Canaan
included a mixture of indigenous peoples and nomads,
Semites, Mesopotamians, and Indo-Europeans; on the
conscious level, a nation was invented in it.
This imagined
community became more and more imagined during two
thousand years of Jewish exile. In every Jewish
dispersal there were mixed marriages and conversions
as a result of which the ethnic identity of those
who were dispersed became irrelevant. It was
precisely because of this that Jewish identity
coalesced into national identity, dependent on
common traditions and destinies, not on common
blood.45
And the concept of nationhood, freed from its
dependence on ethnic traits, was also freed during
two thousand years of exile from any dependence on
territory, and even from dependence on a common
language. Contrary to Marx’s famous dictum,
consciousness determines being.46
Thus, the State
of Israel is defined as a Jewish state, not as an
Israeli state. There is no Israeli nation; there is
a Jewish nation, dispersed throughout the world.47
You are no less Jewish if you are not Israeli, and
the Jews living in Israel are not a “people” in the
ethnic sense. The modern Jewish nation-state is
therefore the realization of the concept of
nationality invented in the Bible and refined in the
Diaspora. Races, peoples, tribes, civilizations,
languages, kingdoms–they have all existed, as
Genesis tells us, since the dawn of history; but not
a nation. Belonging to the imagined community called
“nation” is a revolutionary possibility proposed by
the Bible, and this proposal is what in time shaped
Europe.
Supra-national
powers shaped Europe until the end of the eighteenth
century,48
in the same way as superpowers, alliances, and
supra-national dynamics have shaped and continue to
shape the world today.49
But we must not conclude from this that the upsurge
of European nationalism in the nineteenth century
was what gave rise to the concept of nationalism.
Until the nineteenth century, Europe had
preferred
to define itself according to supra-national
categories (as citizens of an empire, as Catholics
or as Protestants), or sub-national (as vassals of a
principality or as inhabitants of regions), and they
preferred this for a thousand and one good and
not-so-good reasons. But as hosts of the Jews and as
students of the Bible–since Europe’s adoption of
Christianity, and all the more so since the
Reformation–they were aware of the concept of
nationalism and its physical embodiment, and always
reacted to it with words and persecution.
Napoleon’s
conquests at the beginning of the nineteenth century
provoked a nationalistic reaction from Spain to
Russia, and this is clearly the starting point for
the spread of modern European nationalism. But to
tell the story of the spread of European nationalism
in the nineteenth century as a story of the
birth of
the concept of nationalism is to fudge the truth not
only as a historian but also as a philosopher. A
philosophical discussion of the idea of nationalism
demands recognition that it is indeed an idea–not
merely a reactionary emotional symptom.
Why did Berlin
have the reputation of being a liberal who
recognized the significance of nationalism? Perhaps
because of the rhetoric he employed when he referred
to nationalism: The rhetoric of astonishment at its
very existence, and astonishment that all the
leading philosophers of the nineteenth century did
not recognize as he did the significance of the
phenomenon. “No significant thinkers known to me,”
he wrote, “predicted for it [nationalism] a future
in which it would play an even more dominant role.”50
To be sure, “no social or political thinker in the
nineteenth century was unaware of nationalism as a
dominant movement of his age,” but, “in the second
half of the [nineteenth] century, indeed up to the
First World War, it was thought to be waning.”51
So all these philosophers proved to be remarkably
short-sighted, because “the rise of nationalism is
today a world-wide phenomenon, probably the
strongest single factor in the newly established
states, and in some cases among the minority
populations of the older nations.”52
This is a case
of the pot calling the kettle black. The
short-sightedness among nineteenth-century
philosophers concerning the flourishing of
nationalism in the twentieth century was no more
astonishing than Berlin’s short-sightedness
concerning the post-nationalist dynamic that began
at the end of World War II. The flooding of the
United States and Europe with millions of immigrants
(Muslims and others), and the demands from the
radical Left for a “multi-cultural” definition of
citizenship; the renewed delight in Marxism (the
negation of nationalism) after the student riots of
1968; the globalization of market forces that
developed at the expense of national economies; and
the media globalization of the age of television and
pop music that developed at the expense of national
culture–all these processes together created the
post-nationalist order in front of Berlin’s very
eyes. When he wrote about nationalism in the
seventies, he did not predict and could not have
predicted the world’s entry into the Internet age
and the unification of Europe at the turn of the
century. But the period in which he wrote about
nationalism was enough of a post-nationalistic
period even without the Internet and the euro. If he
had taken serious account of nationalism, he would
have dealt with the post-nationalist arguments that
became the intellectual
bon ton of his generation.
There are two
reasons for this short-sightedness. The first is
that Berlin was firmly planted in the first half of
the twentieth century and did not clean off his
spectacles in the second half. The totalitarian
setting that shaped his youth continued to condition
his thinking in later years. From his perspective,
eighteenth-century enlightenment and
nineteenth-century nationalism were two opposite but
complementary trends that gave rise to Bolshevism,
Fascism, and Nazism. Volatile enlightenment ends in
Bolshevism, volatile nationalism ends in Fascism and
Nazism. There is truth in this, but a truth that
became irrelevant in the middle of the twentieth
century. The debate on nationalism in our
liberal-democratic age, appearing more and more to
be a post-nationalist age, is a debate that Berlin
was unprepared for.
The second
reason: He was not a pluralist. If he had been, he
would have understood that nationalism (as long as
it does not descend into chauvinism) is essentially
pluralistic, since it advances particular
identities. Giuseppe Mazzini–the shining example of
nineteenth-century European nationalism–wanted to
help all
nationalist movements, not only the
Italian national movement. And that is the
nationalist attitude at its best. The English
nationalist does not want the Japanese to be more
English. He wants a world in which there is Zen
Buddhism and Haiku, martial arts, and Noh
theater–and he wants to have something to give to
the Japanese. He will have nothing to offer if he is
not English.
The close link between nationalism and pluralism is
the philosophy of Herder in a nutshell. Berlin
admired Herder, but not for the right reasons.
Herder, who coined the expression “spirit of the
people” (volksgeist),
was a national
pluralist, and Berlin invented a Herder who
was not a nationalist: Ostensibly a pluralist but in
fact a liberal.53
Just as he created the Romanticists in his own
image, Berlin created Herder in his own image;
Romanticism and nationalism did not appear to him as
opinions but as reflections of his opinion. Worse,
according to his own doctrine, it was actually up to
him to preserve the link between nationalism and
pluralism, because nationalism, in his conception,
was born from Romanticism, and Romanticism, in his
conception, championed pluralism. In other words,
precisely because of his two basic premises
(nationalism is Romantic, and Romanticism is
pluralistic) he should have reached the conclusion
that nationalism and pluralism are closely linked.
This is what he would have concluded, had he been a
pluralist.
V
A
thinker who writes about other thinkers rather than
expressing his own worldview explicitly is likely to
be considered a pluralist. Berlin’s writings evoked,
as mentioned, a sense of roaming widely among
currents of ideas, and so the hedgehog passed
himself off as a fox. How successful the illusion
was can be ascertained by reading the praise
typically heaped on Berlin and the criticism
typically leveled against him. First, the praise.
“Isaiah Berlin’s essays in the history of ideas are
not written from a point of view,” Roger Hausheer
wrote in the introduction to one of the anthologies
of Berlin’s essays. “They are not intended directly
to illustrate or support (or for that matter attack
or undermine) any single historical or political
theory, doctrine or ideology… they are wholly
exploratory and undogmatic.… Less, perhaps, than any
other thinker does Berlin suppose himself in
possession of some simple truth, and then proceed to
interpret and rearrange the world in the light of
it.”54
As for the criticism: “I cannot perceive any solid
logical or philosophical ground in his work for
exonerating him from the charge of relativism,”
Norman Podhoretz wrote two years after Berlin’s
death.55
This is the
conventional image that is attached to Berlin by
adherents and critics alike. The man lectured and
wrote, so it would seem, not “from a point of view”
but with a bird’s-eye view, and therefore you won’t
find any tendentious interpretation in him of the
history of Western thought. This absence of
tendentiousness is sometimes attributed to him as a
virtue (as Hausheer would have it) and at other
times as a vice (as Podhoretz claims). Yet his
objective, Olympian view that admirers and
detractors of Berlin ascribed to him was only an
affect.
Let us ignore
the affect and deal with the content. Was Berlin’s
philosophical argument, as is normally thought, a
pluralistic one? In an interview he gave in 1988,
Berlin summarized what he regarded as a pluralistic
outlook: “One can choose one life or the other, but
not both; and there is no over-arching criterion to
determine the right choice; one chooses as one
chooses, neither life can objectively be called
superior to the other.”56
This leads to the practical, political conclusion:
“Room must be made for a life in which some values
may turn out to be incompatible, so that if
destructive conflict is to be avoided compromises
have to be effected, and a minimum degree of
toleration, however reluctant, becomes
indispensable.”57
We would appear
to be faced with a multicultural argument concerning
the pluralistic recognition of the validity of
different ways of life. But when Berlin elaborates
his argument, it turns out that he means something
different: “I believe, in other words, that some of
the ultimate values by which men live cannot be
reconciled or combined…. You cannot combine full
liberty with full equality… Justice and mercy,
knowledge and happiness can collide,” and therefore
“the idea of a perfect solution of human problems–of
how to live, cannot be coherently conceived….
Utopian solutions are in principle incoherent and
unimaginable… so there have to be choices. Choices
can be very painful. If you choose A, you are
distressed to lose B. There is no avoiding choices
between ultimate human values…. All fanatical belief
in the possibility of a final solution, no matter
how reached, cannot but lead to suffering, misery,
blood, terrible oppression.”58
In other words,
Berlin is not speaking about a clash of
systems of
values (or cultures), but about a clash of values
within each
system, within
each culture. All normative systems contain,
according to him, absolute values that are mutually
exclusive–values such that the choice of one of them
is an unavoidable impingement on another. The choice
between absolute and incompatible values must be
made, but it is not a choice that can be
explained
according to any system of values. In fact, every
choice of one value at the expense of another value
in the same system makes the system irrelevant. For,
according to Berlin, one is not likely–indeed one is
not able–to apply any particular value system but
only to apply a few values that do not constitute a
system and are not derived from any one system.
If you choose,
for example, the value of equality at the expense of
liberty, this does not mean that you have chosen a
socialistic value system; you have chosen only one
socialist value, not other socialist values, like
the sanctification of technological progress or of
productive labor. And if you choose, let’s suppose,
the value of mercy at the expense of justice, this
does not mean that you have chosen Christianity; the
value you chose is
incidentally Christian; you did not
choose it because it is a Christian value, but
because you also, like
the Christians, subscribe to it. As a value system,
Christianity is foreign to us. You may not believe
in Christ, and Christian value terms such as
“grace,” “guilt,” “absolution,” and the heavenly or
hellish “hereafter” may mean nothing to you. So you
are for equality, but not socialism, and you are for
mercy, but not Christianity. You have made for
yourself, as Tolstoy did, a private, homemade ethos.
Tolstoy was a Christian who did not go to church, a
socialist who opposed technological progress, and a
Buddhist who did not practice Buddhist meditation.
He chose values, not value systems–and so, in
Berlin’s opinion, should you.
Therefore,
Berlin does not accept the validity of any
particular value system. He only recognizes
individual moral decisions based on a private voice
of conscience. This is an
eclectic ethos, not a
pluralistic
ethos, since pluralism demands recognition of
the validity of competing value
systems.
Had he been a
pluralist, Berlin would have said something like
this: Christianity offers us a religious ethic,
whereas Buddhism and socialism offer us an atheistic
ethic. Christianity and Buddhism offer us redemption
of the individual soul, whereas socialism offers us
social redemption. Christianity and socialism
developed in the West, whereas Buddhism developed in
the East. Well, even though I am an atheist, I
recognize the independent validity of religions,
therefore I recognize the independent validity of
the Christian ethic; even though I am an
individualist, I recognize the independent validity
of collective theories of redemption, and therefore
recognize the independent validity of the socialist
ethic; and even though I am a Westerner, I recognize
the independent validity of eastern cultures,
therefore I recognize the independent validity of
the Buddhist ethic. I do not agree with any of these
three value systems, but I will defend their right
to exist because cultural, religious, and political
diversity–the diversity
itself–is my ethos.
But Berlin does
not accept the independent validity of value
systems. He accepts, as noted, only the validity of
values that float in a moral space, devoid of
context, and subject to the choice of private
conscience. The ethical man, in Berlin’s doctrine,
is a man exempt
from cultural, religious, and political
pluralism, since he is not required to accept the
independent value and justification of value
systems.
A consequence of
this is Berlin’s famous distinction between
“positive liberty” and “negative liberty.” Positive
liberty is the consummation of one value system or
another, whereas negative liberty is emancipation
from oppression.59
Berlin favored negative liberty and condemned every
form of positive liberty on the grounds that every
consummation of a value system involves aggressive
intolerance by those who consummate it against those
who have no interest in doing the same.
An ethos that
allows only negative freedom, however, is not
pluralism but liberalism. Let us return to the
practical conclusion that Berlin drew from his
ethic: “If destructive conflict is to be avoided
compromises have to be effected, and a minimum
degree of toleration, however reluctant, becomes
indispensable.” That is to say, the only acceptable
regime is a regime of conflict-neutralizing
arrangements. Such a regime makes the rules of the
game to which every value system of every group or
community in the country must be subject. It is a
“tolerant” regime only towards those who obey it; it
is intolerant of any other alternative. Only liberal
democracy is legitimate; only the world of negative
liberty is justifiable.
Berlin’s
reputation as a political philosopher may derive
from the fact that he said the right thing at the
right time. He addressed himself to an audience that
had been traumatized by Nazism, Bolshevism, and
Fascism, and that found in his anti-totalitarian
message a declaration that there was no need to
delve into its meaning in order to adopt it
enthusiastically. But what sounded like the very
voice of moral reason to ears that were still
ringing from World War II sounds evasive to our
ears.
Not all liberal
philosophers or liberal regimes of the last few
generations are afflicted with lack of clarity. The
present global struggle between the United States
and Islamic extremists is not a struggle between
pluralists (foxes) and dogmatists (hedgehogs), but
between hedgehogs and hedgehogs–between two
irreconcilable ideologies. Not for a moment has the
current American government persuaded itself or its
voters or the rest of the world that it is fighting
its enemies under the banner of pluralism. The
liberal superpower employs a non-pluralistic
ambition to impose the liberal-democratic worldview
on the entire world, a dogmatic faith in its
rightness, a missionary sense of saving the world, a
messianic ambition.
This ideological
candor that typifies the non-hypocritical policy of
the United States in its struggles against the
enemies of liberalism–this direct admission that
liberalism is as aggressive as any other ethos that
purports to represent truth and justice–is absent
from Berlin’s “pluralistic” writings. The
philosophical challenge of justifying liberalism
arises when the liberal is no longer a victim
of despotic regimes complaining about
the wrong done to him and persuading himself that
his complaint is moral philosophy; it arises when he
becomes a member of the ruling camp who bears moral
responsibility. Only then does the contradiction
between slogans about “pluralism” and the sincere
ambition for ideological and political hegemony
become clear to a liberal.
We would look in
vain for Berlin to tackle the question of a
liberal’s responsibility that arises when liberalism
rules. Berlin’s consciousness was shaped by the
biography of a victim; the Bolsheviks who persecuted
well-to-do families like his, and the Nazis who
persecuted Jews like him, accustomed him to see the
political from the simple and conceptually
comfortable viewpoint of being helpless–that is, not
responsible. The category that encompasses
“totalitarianism” excused Berlin from a discerning
discussion of the anti-liberal ideologies in Russia,
Germany, Italy, and Spain. Is there no difference
between the totalitarian ideology that was
influenced by the rationalist utopianism of the
Enlightenment (Bolshevism) and the totalitarian
ideology that championed the values of the
counter-Enlightenment (Fascism)?
According to
Berlin, apparently not. We therefore have no way of
knowing if the opposite of pluralism, in Berlin’s
doctrine, is rationalist universalism or
irrationalist chauvinism. There is nothing in common
between the enemies of pluralism against whom Berlin
spoke, except radicalism. But radicalism is a
temperament receptive to any content–not only to a
rationalist-utopian “hedgehogish” content. Hitler
and Mussolini were not hedgehogs but foxes, if being
a fox means being opposed to the rationalist-utopian
vision of the Enlightenment. “There are indeed
dangers in the hedgehog, but we must not forget that
there are dangers in the fox as well,” Ronald
Dworkin reminds us. “Moral crimes have been
justified by appeal to the opposite idea, that
important political values necessarily conflict,
that no choice among these can be defended as the
only right choice.”60
Thus the
dichotomies proposed by Berlin–hedgehog/fox,
monism/pluralism, positive liberty/negative
liberty–are charming in the harmful sense of the
word. Their charm is ostensibly the charm of
generalities that muddy the conceptual waters. When
you free Berlin’s “pluralistic” argument from the
spellbinding, rhetorical flow of his essays and
attempt to summarize it, you discover his moral and
political pallor. He does not equip us properly for
the war we are in, but precisely for this reason it
is important to remember him. He reminds us of what
the West ignored in the second half of the twentieth
century, when it was complacent and fell asleep at
its post.
________________
Assaf Inbari
is an essayist and literary critic.
Notes
1. Isaiah Berlin,
Russian Thinkers, ed. Henry Hardy and
Aileen Kelly (London: Penguin, 1994).
2. Isaiah Berlin, “Empirical Propositions and
Hypothetical Statements,”
Mind 59, pp. 289-312; “Logical
Translation,”
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
50 (1949-1950), pp. 157-188; Isaiah Berlin,
“Political Ideas in the Twentieth Century,”
Foreign Affairs
28 (1950), pp. 351-385; “Socialism and Socialist
Theories,” Chambers’s
Encyclopedia, vol. 12 (London: Newnes,
1950), pp. 638-650.
3. Michael Ignatieff,
Isaiah Berlin: A Life (New York: Henry
Holt, 1998), p.
4.
4. Ignatieff, Isaiah
Berlin: A Life, p. 4.
5. Among Berlin’s occasional forays into side
issues, it is worth noting his essays “The ‘Naïveté’
of Verdi,” in Against
the Current: Essays in the History of Ideas,
ed. Henry Hardy (Princeton: Princeton,
2001), pp. 287-295; “Artistic Commitment: A Russian
Legacy,” in The Sense
of Reality: Studies in Ideas and Their History,
ed. Henry Hardy (New York: Farrar, Straus and
Giroux, 1997), pp. 194-231, and also the cameo essay
that he wrote about Einstein, Churchill, Roosevelt,
Weizmann, Ben-Gurion, Aldous Huxley, J.L. Austin,
and others, most of which were incorporated in an
anthology, Personal
Impressions, ed. Henry Hardy (London:
Hogarth, 1980).
6. Isaiah Berlin, The
Hedgehog and the Fox: An Essay on Tolstoy’s View of
History (Chicago: Ivan R. Dee, 1993),
pp. 3-4. Berlin took the graphic contrast between
“foxes” and “hedgehogs,” as he himself states in the
opening sentence of the essay, from the ancient
Greek poet, Archilochus, who wrote: “The fox knows
many things, but the hedgehog knows one big thing.”
See Berlin, The
Hedgehog and the Fox, p. 3.
7. In fact, there is no need for any more
metaphorical animals in order to understand the
superficiality of the distinction between
“hedgehogs” and “foxes,” for there are many types of
“hedgehogs” and many types of “foxes”; the
differences between “hedgehog” and “hedgehog” and
the differences between “fox” and “fox” are not
great and are of less importance than the
differences between each “hedgehog” and each “fox.”
Steven Lukes, for instance, pointed out that it is
possible to divide Berlin’s hedgehog into at least
four separate divisions: “positivists,”
“universalists,” “rationalists,” and “monists”;
Steven Lukes, “An Unfashionable Fox,” in
The Legacy of Isaiah
Berlin, eds. Mark Lilla, Ronald Dworkin,
and Robert Silvers (New York: New York Review of
Books, 2001), pp. 43-57.
8. Jacob L. Talmon, The
Origins of Totalitarian Democracy
(London: Sphere Books, 1970). According to Talmon’s
introduction, he came up with the idea for the book
ten years previously. Max Horkheimer and Theodor W.
Adorno, Dialectic of
Enlightenment, trans. John Cumming (New
York: Seabury, 1972).
9. Karl R. Popper, The
Open Society and Its Enemies (Princeton:
Princeton, 1966).
10. Isaiah Berlin, The
Roots of Romanticism (Princeton:
Princeton, 1999),
pp. 17-18.
11. Isaiah Berlin, “The Romantic Revolution: A
Crisis in the History of Modern Thought,” in
The Sense of Reality,
p. 170.
12. Berlin, “The Romantic Revolution,” p. 171.
13. Berlin, “The Romantic Revolution,” p. 172.
14. Moreover, Antigone in fact depicts a conflict
between three absolute values, because the burial of
the brother (Polinyces) is mandatory not merely
because of the absolute value of family loyalty, but
also because of the absolute value of honoring a
decree of the gods. We are therefore faced with a
double conflict: (a) between the familial duty and
the civic duty; and (b) between the religious duty
and the civil duty. This double conflict between two
opposing values is presented not only in the
dramatic confrontation between Antigone and Creon
but also in the internal dilemma of each of the two,
for both belong to the same family, the same city,
and the same religion. In other words, the three
conflicting values are perceived as absolute values,
each in its own right, in the eyes of both Antigone
and Creon.
15. “A grievous ill it is not to consent [to
slaughter his daughter Iphigenia],” shouts
Aeschylus’s Agamemnon, “and grievous too if I must
slay my child, the jewel of my home, defiling at the
altar-side a father’s hands in streaming blood from
a stricken virgin’s throat! Is either course not
full of misery?” “Agamemnon,”
The Plays of Aeschylus,
trans. Walter Headlam and C.E.S. Headlam (London:
George Bell and Sons, 1909), p. 160. “Is either
course not full of misery?” Morally it is
impossible. The absolute values are not compatible.
16. Nathan Spiegel, The
History of Ancient Ethics (Jerusalem:
Magnes, 1985), p. 43. [Hebrew]
17. See, for example, the anthology
Tragic Themes in
Western Literature, ed. Cleanth Brooks
(New Haven: Yale, 1955), which includes articles on
the tragic elements in Shakespeare, Racine,
Dostoevsky, Ibsen, George Bernard Shaw, and
T.S. Eliot.
18. Berlin, “The Romantic Revolution,” p. 175.
19. Berlin, The Roots
of Romanticism, p. 12.
20. Berlin, “The Romantic Revolution,” p. 183.
21. Berlin, “The Romantic Revolution,” p. 182.
22. The Chinese and the Indians possess, according
to their doctrine, complete and perfect eternal
knowledge. Taoist law on the “Five Principles” of
nature and on the two opposite and complementary
powers–yin and yang–that operate universally, and
Confucian law that regulates all familial and social
relationships were integrated by the Chinese into a
general philosophy that is all-knowing and
all-resolving. Shankara, Patanjali, and other Hindu
philosophers based the Brahmin rituals in an
omniscient metaphysics (at the center of which was
the transcendental “Absolute,” the Brahmin, of which
the entire “relative” world of phenomena is an
offshoot) and on an all-resolving meditation that
brings anyone who practices it correctly and
assiduously to perfect “enlightenment” that is
perfect wisdom and perfect happiness. Every aspect
of life, even sex, is a subject of technical
exercise on the path to perfect accomplishment.
23. Berlin, “The Romantic Revolution,” pp. 185-186.
24. Berlin, “The Romantic Revolution,” p. 187.
25. Berlin, “The Romantic Revolution,” p. 187.
26. Berlin, “The Romantic Revolution,” p. 190.
27. Berlin, “The Romantic Revolution,” p. 191.
28. Berlin himself noted this, but instead of
insisting on the difference between existentialism
and Romanticism, he argued that existentialism was
no more than the modern continuation of Romanticism,
see Berlin, “The Romantic Revolution,” p. 190.
29. A few examples from English poetry: Coleridge’s
poem “Frost at Midnight” (1798), Byron’s poem
“Darkness” (1816), Shelley’s poem “To Night” (1821)
and Keats’s poems “Sleep and Poetry” (1816), “In
Drear-Nighted December” (1817), “Bright Star”
(1819), “Why Did I Laugh Tonight?” (1819), and “To
Sleep” (1819).
30. Existence is not cosmic intelligence (as claimed
by philosophers from Plato to Hegel), but a cosmic
ego as claimed by Johann Gottlieb Fichte,
The Vocation of Man,
trans. Roderick Chisholm (Indianapolis:
Bobbs-Merrill, 1956), or cosmic will as Arthur
Schopenhauer contends; see Arthur Schopenhauer,
The World as Will and
Representation, trans. E.F.J. Payne (New
York: Dover, 1958). In Schopenhauer, this concept of
cosmic will took on a monstrous character; a
crushing force, irrational and immoral, that can
only be submitted to or avoided by spiritual
self-castration, as the Buddhists do.
31. Immanuel Kant, “An Answer to the Question: What
Is Enlightenment?” in
Kant’s Political Writings, ed. Hans
Reiss, trans. H.B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge,
1991), p. 54.
32. This is why, for the Romanticists, poetry became
a paradigm of all literary writing. Fiction had to
become poetic, and in the hands of Friedrich
Schlegel even philosophy became a form of
fragmentary, poetical expression, reflective poetry.
33. The word “sublime” got its terrifying meaning
which became central in the Romantic period, from
Edmund Burke. See Edmund Burke,
A Philosophical Enquiry
into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and
Beautiful: And Other Pre-revolutionary Writings,
ed. David Womersley (London: Penguin, 1998), and
Immanuel Kant, Critique
of Judgment, trans. Werner S. Pluhar
(Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987).
34. Avishai Margalit, “The Crooked Timber of
Nationalism,” in The
Legacy of Isaiah Berlin, p. 150.
35. Richard Wollheim, “Berlin and Zionism,” in
The Legacy of Isaiah
Berlin, p. 168.
36. Isaiah Berlin, “The Bent Twig: On the Rise of
Nationalism,” in The
Crooked Timber of Humanity, ed. Henry
Hardy (Princeton: Princeton, 1990), p. 245.
37. Berlin, “The Bent Twig: On the Rise of
Nationalism,” p. 254.
38. As Avishai Margalit says: “For Berlin the
emotional underpinnings of nationalism are the most
important element in nationalism, more important
than the set of beliefs that nourishes it.” In other
words, for Berlin, nationalism is emotion, not a
worldview; see Margalit, “The Crooked Timber,” p.
150.
39. Three thousand years ago–if our reference point
is the establishment of David’s kingdom. It is
possible to choose an earlier reference point (the
period of the judges or even the period of the
fathers, if the period of the fathers is not a
biblical myth), or a later reference point (the
period of Isaiah ben Amotz, or the period of the
return to Zion under the leadership of Ezra and
Nechemia), and we might well ask, who created
whom–the people of Israel the Bible or the Bible the
people of Israel. One way or the other, the
self-definition of the biblical people of Israel
(and Jews down the generations) was and remains a
national definition–not tribal, not racial, not
political citizenship, not communal, and not
religious in the non-national sense of other
religions.
40. Esther 3:8.
41. In this context, attention should be paid to the
arguments of Anthony D. Smith, who remarked that the
Hebrews of the biblical period, together with the
Armenians and perhaps even the Japanese and the
Koreans of the Middle Ages represented pre-modern
“social formations” that closely approximated the
standard modern definition of “nation.” See Anthony
D. Smith, Nationalism
and Modernism: A Critical Survey of Recent Theories
of Nations and Nationalism (London:
Routledge, 1998), p. 190.
42. Ethiopia, Egypt, and Canaan sprang from the
loins of Ham, according to Genesis 10:6-14.
43. Benedict Anderson,
Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and
Spread of Nationalism (London: Verso,
1991), pp. 5-6.
44. Ernest Gellner,
Thought and Change (London: Weidenfeld
and Nicholson, 1964), p. 168.
45. Berlin himself stressed this point in a letter
he wrote on January 23, 1959 in response to
Ben-Gurion’s question, “Who is a Jew?” “We should
make a man to be a Jew, if he were in most respects
identified with a Jewish community, despite the fact
that his mother may be an unconverted non-Jewess,”
wrote Berlin to Ben-Gurion; see
Who is a Jew? An
Anthology of Responses of the Sages of Israel
(Tel Aviv: Ben-Gurion House), p. 80. Berlin was one
of five Jewish intellectuals to whom Ben-Gurion sent
a letter in which he asked them to give their
opinion concerning the national status of a man born
to a Jewish father and a non-Jewish mother (a
question that in hindsight acquired the title “Who
is a Jew?”), after the resignation from his
government of religious ministers in the summer of
1958 in protest over the interior minister’s
decision to register those seeking citizenship as
“Jews” on the basis of a simple declaration, without
requiring them to submit proof, as they had
previously been required to do. Berlin’s reply is
instructive for our purposes, since it shows that he
considered Jewish identity to be dependent on a
conscious belonging and not a factual-biological
one.
46. Karl Marx, A
Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy,
trans. N. I. Stone (Chicago: Charles H. Kerr, 1904),
pp. 11-12.
47. Of the 13 million Jews alive today, 5.7 million
live in the United States, 5 million in Israel, and
the remainder (2.3 million) are dispersed in other
countries. English is the language of 6.5 million
Jews (Americans, Canadians, English, Australians,
New Zealanders, and South Africans), which is to say
that 50 percent of Jews living today are English
speakers, 38.5 percent of them are Hebrew speakers,
and the remainder (11.5 percent) speak other
languages (the most prominent of these being
Russian, French, and Spanish).
48. The Hellenist Empire, the Roman Empire, the
Catholic Church, the Carolingian Empire, and the
supra-national royal dynasties.
49. The ussr, the
Eastern Bloc, the UN,
nato, the EEC, and globalization.
50. Isaiah Berlin, “Nationalism: Past Neglect and
Present Power,” in
Against the Current, p. 337.
51. Berlin, “The Bent Twig: On the Rise of
Nationalism,” p. 243.
52. Berlin, “The Bent Twig: On the Rise of
Nationalism,” p. 251.
53. As Aileen Kelly points out: “His reaction
against the despotic consequences of historical
teleologies rooted in Enlightenment thought led him
to identify too closely with the
Counter-Enlightenment in the form of Vico, Herder,
and Hamann; his sympathy for these irregulars having
blinded him to irreconcilable differences between
their irrationalism and his own liberal pluralism.”
Aileen Kelly, “A Revolutionary Without Fanaticism,”
in The Legacy of Isaiah
Berlin, p. 4. And as Mark Lilla puts it:
“The fundamental core of the Counter-Enlightenment
actually was its hostility to enlightenment–as such.
And therefore it was hostile to the basic moral and
political values which Berlin himself defended.”
Mark Lilla, “Wolves and Lambs,” in
The Legacy of Isaiah
Berlin, p. 38. That is to say: Berlin
was a liberal, and as such he was the successor of
the Enlightenment (which he deprecated), and not the
successor of the counter-Enlightenment (which he
lauded).
54. Roger Hausheer, Introduction to
Against the Current,
p. xiii.
55. Norman Podhoretz, “A Dissent on Isaiah Berlin,”
Commentary
(February 1999), p. 34.
56. Ramin Jahanbegloo,
Conversations with Isaiah Berlin
(London: P. Halban, 1992), p. 45.
57. Jahanbegloo,
Conversations with Isaiah Berlin, p. 44.
58. Jahanbegloo,
Conversations with Isaiah Berlin, pp.
142-143.
59. Isaiah Berlin, “Two Concepts of Liberty,” in
Four Essays on Liberty
(Oxford: Oxford, 1969), pp. 118-172.
60. Ronald Dworkin, “Do Liberal Values Conflict?” in
The Legacy of Isaiah
Berlin, p. 75.
|