CHAPTER I.
OF THE PRINCIPLE OF UTILITY
I. Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two
sovereign masters, pain and pleasure. It is
for them alone to point out what we ought to do, as well as
to determine what we [actually] shall do. On the one hand
the standard of right and wrong, on the other the chain of
causes and effects, are fastened to their throne. They
govern us in all we do, in all we say, in all we think:
every effort we can make to throw off our subjection, will
serve but to demonstrate and confirm it. In words a man may
pretend to abjure their empire: but in reality he will
remain subject to it all the while. The principle of
utility recognizes this subjection, and assumes it for
the foundation of that system the object of which is to rear
the fabric of felicity by the hands of reason and of law.
Systems, which attempt to question it, deal in sounds
instead of sense, in caprice instead of reason, in darkness
instead of light.
But enough of metaphor and declamation: it is not by such
means that moral science is to be improved.
II . . . By the principle of utility is meant that
principle which approves or disapproves of every action
whatsoever, according to the tendency which it appears to
have to augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose
interest is in question: or, what is the same thing in other
words, to promote or to oppose that happiness. I say of
every action whatsoever; and therefore not only of every
action of a private individual, but of every measure of
government.
III. By utility is meant that property in any object,
whereby it tends to produce benefit, advantage, pleasure,
good, or happiness, (all this . . . comes to the same thing)
or (what again comes to the same thing) to prevent the
happening of mischief, pain, evil, or unhappiness to the
party whose interest is considered: if that party be the
community in general, then the happiness of the community:
if a particular individual, then the happiness of that
individual.
IV. The interest of the community . . . is . . . the sum
total of the interests of the several members who compose
it.
V. It is vain to talk of the interest of the community,
without understanding what is the interest of the
individual. A thing is said to promote the interest, or to
be for the interest, of an individual, when it tends
to add to the sum total of his pleasures: or, what comes to
the same thing, to diminish the sum total of his pains.
VI. An action then may be said to be conformable to the
principle of utility...when the tendency it has to augment
the happiness of the community is greater than any it has to
diminish it. . . .
X. Of an action that is conformable to the principle of
utility, one may always say either that it is one that ought
to be done, or at least that it is not one that ought not to
be done. One may say also, that it is right it should be
done; at least that it is not wrong it should be done: that
it is a right action; at least that it is not a wrong
action. When thus interpreted, the words ought, and
right and wrong, and others of that stamp have
a meaning: when [interpreted] otherwise, they have none.
...
CHAPTER IV.
VALUE OF A LOT OF PLEASURE OR PAIN, HOW TO BE MEASURED.
I. Pleasures then, and the avoidance of pains, are the
ends which the legislator has in view: it behooves him
therefore to understand their value. . . .
V. To take an exact account . . . of the general tendency
of any act. . . .[:]
Sum up all the values of the pleasures on the one
side, and those of all the pains on the other. The balance,
if it be on the side of pleasure, will give the good
tendency of the act upon the whole. . . .
Take an account of the number of persons whose
interests appear to be concerned. . . . Take the balance;
which, if on the side of pleasure, will give the general
good tendency of the act, with respect to the total number
or community of individuals concerned; if on the side of
pain, the general evil tendency, with respect to the
same community. |