"The Course of World
History" From Hegel,
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Reason in History. trans. Robert S. Hartman, ed. Robert S.
Hartman (Indianapolis, IN: The Bobbs-Merrill
Company, Inc., 1953), 68-71.
The German philosopher Georg Hegel
(1770-1831) was born in Stuttgart and studied in Tübingen.
After various teaching posts he became professor of philosophy in Berlin.
Hegel devoted much of his thought to the philosophy of history. An
"Idealist," Hegel viewed history as a dialectical process of
thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, which amounted to the evolution of Spirit,
or God. Hegel's view of the struggling progression of the Spirit seems partly
indebted to Schleiermacher's emphasis on the primacy of religious
consciousness in human affairs; and Karl Marx, while rejecting Hegel's
"Idealism," nevertheless appropriated his vision of history as an
evolutionary process. Historical change, seen
abstractly, has long been understood generally as involving a progress
towards the better, the more perfect. Change in nature, no matter how
infinitely varied it is, shows only a cycle of constant repetition. In nature
nothing new happens under the sun, and in this respect the multiform play of
her products leads to boredom. One and the same permanent character continuously
reappears, and all change reverts to it. Only the changes in the realm of
Spirit create the novel. This characteristic of Spirit suggested to man a feature entirely different from that of
nature--the desire toward perfectibility. This principle, which brings
change itself under laws, has been badly received by religions such as the
Catholic and also by states which desire as their true right to be static or
at least stable. When the mutability of secular things, such as states, is conceded
on principle, then religion, as religion of truth, is excluded. On the other
hand, one leaves undecided whether changes, revolutions, and destructions of
legitimate conditions are not due to accidents, blunders, and, in particular,
the license and evil passions of men. Actually, perfectibility is something
almost as undetermined as mutability in general; it is without aim and
purpose and without a standard of change. The better, the more perfect
towards which it is supposed to attain, is entirely undetermined. The principle of development
implies further that it is based on an inner principle, a presupposed
potentiality, which brings itself into existence. This formal determination
is essentially the Spirit whose scene, property, and sphere of realization is world history. It does not flounder about in the
external play of accidents. On the contrary, it is absolutely determined and
firm against them. But development is also a property of organic natural
objects. Their existence is not merely dependent, subject to external
influences. It proceeds rather from an inner immutable principle, a simple
essence, which first exists as a germ. From this simple existence it brings
forth out of itself differentiations which connect it with other things. Thus
it lives a life of continuous transformation. On the other hand, we may look
at it from the opposite point of view and see in it the preservation of the
organic principle and its form. Thus the organic individual produces itself;
it makes itself, and it makes itself actually into that which it is in itself
(potentially). The development of the organism proceeds in an immediate,
direct (undialectic), unhindered manner. Nothing
can interfere between the concept and its realization, the inherent nature of
the germ and the adaptation of its existence to this nature. It is different
with Spirit. The transition of its potentiality into actuality is mediated
through consciousness and will. These are themselves first immersed in their
immediate organic life; their first object and purpose is this natural
existence as such. But the latter, through its animation by Spirit, becomes
itself infinitely demanding, rich, and strong. Thus Spirit is at war with
itself. It must overcome itself as its own enemy and formidable obstacle.
Development, which in nature is a quiet unfolding, is in Spirit a hard,
infinite struggle against itself. What Spirit wants is to attain its own
concept. But it hides it from itself and is proud and full of enjoyment at
this alienation from itself. Historical development, therefore,
is not the harmless and unopposed simple growth of organic life but hard,
unwilling labor against itself. Furthermore, it is not mere formal
self-development in general, but the production of an end of determined
content. This end we have stated from the beginning: it is Spirit in its
essence, the concept of freedom. This is the fundamental object and hence the
leading principle of development. Through it the development receives meaning
and significance--just as in Roman history Rome is the object and hence the
guiding principle of the inquiry into past events. At the same time, however,
the events arise out of this object and have meaning and content only with
reference to it. There are in world history several
large periods which have passed away, apparently without further development.
Their whole enormous gain of culture has been annihilated and, unfortunately,
one had to start all over from the beginning in order to reach again one of
the levels of culture which had been reached long ago--assisted, perhaps, by
some ruins saved of old treasures--with a new, immeasurable effort of power
and time, of crime and suffering. On the other hand, there are continuing
developments, structures, and systems of culture in particular spheres, rich
in kind and well-developed in every direction. The merely formal view of
development can give preference neither to one
course nor the other; nor can it account for the purpose of that decline of
older periods. It must consider such events, and in particular such
reversals, as external accidents. It can judge the relative advantages only
according to indefinite viewpoints--viewpoints which are relative precisely
because development in general is viewed as the one and only purpose. World history, then, represents
the phases in the development of the principle whose content is the
consciousness of freedom. The analysis of its stages in general belongs to
Logic. That of its particular, its concrete nature, belongs to the Philosophy
of Spirit. Let us only repeat here that the first stage is the immersion of
Spirit in natural life, the second its stepping out
into the consciousness of its freedom. This first emancipation from nature is
incomplete and partial; it issues from immediate naturalness, still refers to
it, and hence is still encumbered by it as one of its elements. The third
stage is the rising out of this still particular form of freedom into pure
universality of freedom, where the spiritual essence attains the
consciousness and feeling of itself. These stages are the fundamental
principles of the universal process. Each is again, within itself, a process
of its own formation. But the detail of this inner dialectic of transition
must be left to the sequel. All we have to indicate here is that
Spirit begins with its infinite possibility, but only its possibility.
As such it contains its absolute content within itself, as its aim and goal,
which it attains only as result of its activity. Then and only then has
Spirit attained its reality. Thus, in existence, progress appears as an
advance from the imperfect to the more perfect. But the former must not only
be taken in abstraction as the merely imperfect, but as that which contains
at the same time its own opposite, the so-called perfect, as germ, as urge
within itself. In the same way, at least in thought, possibility points to
something which shall become real; more precisely, the Aristotelian dynamis is also potentia,
force and power. The imperfect, thus, as the opposite of itself in itself, is
its own antithesis, which on the one hand exists, but, on the other, is
annulled and resolved. It is the urge, the impulse of spiritual life in
itself, to break through the hull of nature, of sensuousness, of its own
self-alienation, and to attain the light of consciousness, namely, its own
self. Hartman, R.S., REASON IN HISTORY:
HEGEL, © 1953. Electronically reproduced by
permission of Pearson Education, Inc., Upper Saddle River, New Jersey. |