Revolution in Political Thought:
Machiavelli,
Hobbes Locke excerpted from An
Intellectual History of Modern Europe by Marvin Perry By the end of the seventeenth century, a revolution
in political thinking had occurred that developed in parallel to the revolution
in Western thinkers’ perception of the physical universe. These political
scientists regarded government as a purely human creation. Its authority did not derive from God, and
its actions should not be measured by values originating in a higher world.
These thinkers argued that churches should exercise no authority in matters of
government, and the state was not responsible for assisting the church in the
saving of souls. The new cosmology and the new political philosophies rested on
their own intellectual foundations, not principles from a higher world
requiring clerical clarification. The sixteenth and seventeenth centuries
witnessed the dissolution of the old medieval political order and the emergence
of the modern, centralized, territorial state. During the Middle Ages kings had to share political
power with feudal lords, the clergy and representative assemblies. People saw
themselves as members of an estate- clergy, aristocracy or commoner- rather
than as citizens of a state. The Church regarded Europe as a commonwealth in
which spiritual concerns prevailed over secular authority. The King received
his power from God and had to rule in accordance with God’s commands as
interpreted by the clergy. In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, kings
successfully asserted their authority over competing powers. Parliaments were
crushed, and lords and ecclesiastical authorities were made subject to royal
control. Features of the modern state
began to emerge. In its maturity, a modern state would be supreme in its own
territory with a strong central government which issues laws that apply
throughout the land; it would maintain and pay a permanent army of professional
soldiers, as well as trained bureaucrats who would collect taxes, enforce laws
and administer justice. It would be a secular state wherein churches would not
determine state policy. Niccolo Machiavelli (1469-1527) This Florentine statesman and political theorist gave
expression to the new direction in which politics was moving in his great works
of political theory The Prince (1513) and Discourses on the First
Decade of Totus Livius (1516). Machiavelli was a keen observer of the
politics of the city-states which fought each other for power in Northern Italy
during the last part of the fifteenth century.
He regarded the Italian city-states, ruled by men whose authority rested
solely on their cunning and effective use of force, as a new phenomenon which
traditional idealistic political theory could not adequately explain. Italian
princes looked to their own interests, employed force ruthlessly, and made no
effort to justify their policies on religious or idealistic grounds. Powerful
cities devoured weaker ones, and diplomacy was riddled with intrigue, betrayal
and bribery. Italy was frequently over run by foreign invaders. Survival
depended upon alertness, cleverness and strength. Medieval theorists had called for an earthly realm
that accorded with standards revealed by God. Classical theorists sought to
base the state on moral norms apprehended by reason. Machiavelli believed that
what people wanted was not a just or virtuous state but a secure and safe one.
He wanted rulers to understand how to preserve and expand the state’s power and
to provide security in a dangerous world. According to the classical ideal state ethics and
politics were one. The state’s purpose was to promote the virtuous life in
accord with natural law. Christians fashioned the earthly city according to
divine commandments revealed in Scripture. Machiavelli
had no patience with theories that sought to shape political life in accordance
with ideal standards. Indeed, utopian visions would bring ruin to the state.
The ruler should do whatever is necessary to protect the state from domestic
and foreign threats and the passions of his subjects. Machiavelli had a bleak vision of human nature. He thought
humans were naturally selfish, corrupt, cowardly, faithless, base, dishonest,
and violent. Deception and coercion are necessary to hold in check this flawed
human nature which threatens civil order. Machiavelli was an empirical
theorist, an inspiration to Bacon. He drew his principles of political behavior
from data. He approached politics in the cold light of reason, free of
illusions about human nature and devoid of speculations about utopia. He warned that rulers who are guided by ideals, show compassion
and attempt to be good will be destroyed by their rivals. The ruler should
ignore issues of morality or immortality and instead choose a course of action
based on his analysis of a particular situation. All means are permitted the prince if the state’s survival is at stake.
The wise prince gives the appearance of being virtuous, for such a pretense
will assist him in governing his subjects. But when the security of the state
requires it, the prince is prepared to abandon all virtue. In the world of
politics, blunders- not crimes- are unpardonable. Machiavelli did not intend to provide guidelines for
a tyrant who merely sought to gain personal power for private ends. He had no
love for despots. Rather, he wanted the prince to identify with the people, to
aspire to do what is best for the state in its quest for survival and
stability. He resorts to terror for reasons of state, never for private
passion, pride, whim or petty revenge. Machiavelli’s interpretation of history and politics
is devoid of any overarching Christian meaning. He even ignored the question of
whether the Prince would be punished on the Day of Judgment for violating
Christian doctrine. He further believed that Christianity’s glorification of
humble and contemplative men who are contemptuous of the worldly life had been
detrimental to the state’s well being. On the other hand, Machiavelli noted
that the rulers of the classical age had valued personal achievement, courage,
strength, pride, glory, civic responsibility and patriotism, fostering the
development of a strong, vigorous republic. To Machiavelli, religion only had
value because it was socially useful. The wise ruler could use religion to
unite his subjects and to promote civic obedience. Rulers employ pious fictions
for worthwhile civic ends. Machiavelli broke with the medieval world’s division
of the universe into higher and lower worlds. He did for political thought what
Galileo had done for scientific thought. Medieval thinkers held that the ruler
derived his power from God and had a religious obligation to govern in
accordance with God’s precepts. The best state assisted in the saving of souls.
Machiavelli ascribed no divine origin or purpose to the state but saw it
entirely as a natural entity. ‘Machiavellian’ has become an adjective used to
describe politicians who will stop at nothing to achieve their political ends,
but Machiavelli’s true significance is understood in his removal of political
thought from a religious frame of reference and his insistence on looking at the
state in the detached and dispassionate manner of a political scientist. Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) Hobbes, an English philosopher and political
theorist, also had a gloomy view of human nature. He rejected religious
interpretations of political life and sought to fashion a theory of the state
that accorded with the reality of the human condition. He paid no mind to
medieval theologians’ belief in political communities which conformed to God’s
revelation, and he regarded the attempts of ancient philosophers to design
commonwealths on an ideal of human perfection as useless utopian dreams. He
sought political arrangements that were realistic and realizable- that accorded
with the way people actually behave. Focusing on the dark side of human nature,
both thinkers believed society was threatened by insatiable human desires and
ambitions. In contrast with the idealistic Plato, who fashioned a state based
on on standards of justice and virtue, the realistic Hobbes fashioned a state
intended to provide security in an unsafe and violent world. Hobbes wrote Leviathan (1651) during the
agonies of the English Civil War. He became convinced that absolute monarchy
was the most logical and desirable form of government. He sought to base his
political theory upon scientific principles. He believed that the construction
of a proper government depends on adherence to set rules as regular and
timeless as the rules of geometry. His basis axioms reflected a bleak view of
human nature: people are innately selfish, grasping, envious , distrustful and
treacherous. Competition and dissension, rather than cooperation, characterize
human relations, and their society will naturally and inevitably disintegrate
into violence. Passion governs action more than reason. People are driven by
avarice to sacrifice peace and virtue to power, but people are also driven by
insecurity and fear to take power to safeguard their lives, property and
status. Hobbes’ theory of government was
intended to contain the strife provoked by a flawed human nature.
Contemporary society is never far removed from the ferocity, fear and
insecurity that marked the state of nature. Hobbes derived the need for the state from human
nature itself. Desiring peace and security, each person contracts to renounce
the freedom of his natural condition. To preserve their lives and property, men
surrender their rights to one ruler, or to an assembly, and agree to submit to
the will of authority. The rulers instill a fear of punishment in the
subjects, for people are dissuaded from harming each other only when they
realize that the punishment outweighs the possiblegain from a criminal act. The
ruler must be granted absolute authority, for if the ruler’s power is shackled,
he cannot protect the lives of the subjects. The people cannot call their ruler
to account; they have no legitimate justification for rebellion. The sovereign
must have absolute power or society will collapse, and the anarchy of the state
of nature will return. The possibility of abuse of sovereign power was
preferable to the alternative of civil war and anarchy. Killing a monarch was
never lawful or praiseworthy. Hobbes’ true significance lies in his secular and
rational approach to politics. He rejects the authority of the church and makes
no attempt to fashion the earthly city in accordance with Christian teaching.
Revealed religion is no longer the source of political authority. Although
Hobbes supported absolute monarchy, he dismissed the idea that the monarch’s
power derived from God. The state was a human invention organized by humans to
deal with human problems, and its legitimacy derived from human authority.
Hobbes rejected the idea that a subject could disobey a ruler’s orders if they
conflicted with divine law. During early modern times, the great expansion of
commerce and capitalism spurred the new individualism already pronounced in
Renaissance culture. Group ties had been shattered by competition and
accelerating social mobility. Hobbes described an emerging society in which
people confronted each other in a competitive economy. In this emerging capitalist society people
are neither bound by a transcendental system of morality nor by the rules and
customs that support a fixed order. Hobbes championed the hereditary absolute
monarchy, holding that only the unlimited authority of a sovereign could
contain the human passions which threatened the social order. Hobbes belief that self-interest dominated human
behavior makes him the first major theorist of modern individualism. His
absolute state is antithetical to the spirit of modern liberalism. Even so, the people, not God, are the source
of the ruler’s authority. John Locke (1632-1704) An English physician, statesman, philosopher and
political theorist, Locke shared Hobbes’ rational and secular approach to
political thought but diverged from Hobbes’ conceptions of human nature and the
state. Locke regarded the individual as
essentially good and rational and rejected Hobbes’ absolute state. Seeking
to preserve individual freedom, Locke advocated constitutional government, in which the power to govern derives
from the consent of the governed and the state’s authority is limited by
agreement with the people. Locke’s
psychological and educational thought was also instrumental in shaping the liberal tradition. Locke’s Second Treatise of Government (1690) was written to vindicate the Glorious
Revolution of 1688 in England. It enunciated the principle of natural rights, attacked arbitrary government, and
affirmed government by consent of the people. He gave theoretical expression to
what many progressive Britons had come to regard as inextricable components of
English tradition- a rejection of monarchical absolutism, parliamentary
government under the rule of law, and protection of private property. Unlike Hobbes who saw human beings as selfish
creatures who promote perpetual strife with their relentless pursuit of
creature comforts, fame and power, Locke held that individuals participate in a
moral order whose existence can be grasped through reason. Locke believed that
rational people can recognize that their behavior ought to correspond to the
requirements of the moral order. They are capable of transcending narrow selfishness and respecting the
inherent dignity of others. Locke believed that the human ‘state of nature’ before the creation of the state had
been free, rational, and equal. God had
not set some people above others. Locke
considered it to be self-evident that all men, because they belong to the same
species and have the same nature, are created equal. One person should not
be place in subjection to another. The law of nature is the law of reason. But since men are capable of acting contrary
to reason, they do violate the law of nature by infringing upon the rights of
others. Since there is no authority to restrain people from such behavior,
wronged parties have the right to punish the evildoer. The degree of punishment
and the amount of reparation should be dictated by reason and conscience and
should be in proportion to the transgression. However a society wherein each
person acts as judge is ripe for further tensions. Therefore, men consent to
organize a civil government and to submit to the will of the majority. Locke
rejects the idea that rulers derive their power from God. He asserts that all legitimate authority derives from the
consent of the majority. Locke regarded people as rational beings endowed by
nature and God with fundamental rights:
the right to their life, liberty and property. Locke’s theory
of natural rights is derived from the ancient stoical conception of natural
law which applies to all human beings. He also drew on the medieval Christian view that God’s
eternal law was a law of reason apprehensible by the mind. In establishing a
government, people do not surrender these natural rights to any authority;
instead the new political society is
formed to recognize and secure these
rights. A ruling authority that attempts to govern absolutely and arbitrarily
fails to fulfill the purpose for which it has been established. Under these
circumstances, the people have the moral right to dissolve the government. This recognition of a law above human law, which
people and governing authorities are obligated to obey, is the cornerstone of
modern liberalism. Freedom exists and is meaningful only if it is bound by the
obligation to achieve a reasonableand moral order. The state is constitutional.
It follows established rules and sets barriers to arbitrary dictates. The
legislature has greater power than the monarch. Locke’s belief in reason and
freedom, his theory of natural rights and his assertion of the right of
rebellion against unjust authority had a profound effect upon the Enlightenment
and the liberal revolutions of the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. His
tenets that property is a natural right and that state interference with
personal property leads to the destruction of liberty also became core
principles of modern liberalism.
|