excerpted
from An Intellectual History of Modern
Europe by Marvin Perry. Chapter Seven- 'The Rise of Ideologies' (pp.
203-242)
Nineteenth Century Ideologies:
Conservatism Liberalism, Socialism
Conservatism: The Value of Tradition
To the traditional rulers of Europe,
the French Revolution had been a great evil that had inflicted a near-fatal
wound on civilization. Disgusted and frightened by revolutionary violence,
terror and warfare, they sought to refute the philosophes'
world-view. To them, natural rights, equality, the goodness of man and
perpetual progress were perverse doctrines that had produced the Terror. In
conservatism they found a political philosophy to counter Enlightenment
ideology and to reassert the importance of authority.
Edmund Burke's Reflections on the French Revolution (1790) was instrumental in
shaping conservative thought. Burke (1729-1797), an Anglo-Irish political
theorist and statesman, wanted to warn his compatriots of the dangers
inherent in the ideology of the revolutionaries. In 1790 he predicted that
the French Revolution would lead to terror and military dictatorship. To Burke, the philosophes
were fanatics armed with pernicious principles- abstract ideas divorced from
historical experience- who had dragged France through the mire of revolution.
The philosophes, entranced by great
discoveries in science, believed that the human mind could also transform
social institutions and ancient traditions according to rational models.
Conservatives regarded them as presumptuous men who recklessly dispensed with
venerable religious and moral beliefs. Conservatives saw the good society in
an idealized medieval past, where the chivalric code of a Christian knight
prevailed, religious values pervaded social and political life, and the
various orders of society- clergy, nobility and commoners- bonded together in
a healthy social organism which successfully balanced liberty and authority.
To Burke, the revolutionaries had
produced anarchy and terror through their arrogant contempt for the past. He
argued that the future is defiled when the past is ignored. He sharply distinguished between the French
Revolution and the earlier British and American Revolutions. Those
revolutions had been attempts to restore traditional liberties that had been
violated by tyrannical governments, not efforts to remake society completely.
Conservatives did not regard human
beings as good by nature. Human
wickedness was not due to a faulty environment; it was at the core of human
nature. The authority of church and state was needed to restrain
humanity's dark and destructive instincts. Tested institutions, traditions and beliefs held evil in check, not
reason. Without these habits inherited from ancestors, the social
order was threatened by sinful human nature. Because monarchy, aristocracy
and the church had endured for centuries, they had proven their worth. The
clergy taught proper rules of conduct, the monarchy preserved order and
property, and aristocrats guarded not only against despotic kings but also
against the tyranny of the majority.
Moderate
conservatives would accept reforms provided that reformers were not
contemptuous of history and tradition, did not seek to level society
according to some artificial or mechanical scheme, and did not move at a pace
that disrupted the social order. For conservatives, society was not a machine
with replaceable parts, but a complex and delicate organism. Tamper with its
vital parts, and it might die.
The art of
politics, according to Burke, requires common sense. The wise statesman
abhors abstract principles and spurns ideal models. Rather, he values the
historical experiences of his nation, and he is concerned with real people in
specific historical situations; he recognizes that institutions and beliefs
do not require theoretical excellence and do not have to meet the test of
reason or nature in order to be useful and beneficial to society. He wrote,
"It is with infinite caution that any man ought to venture upon pulling
down an edifice which has answered in any tolerable degree for ages the
common purposes of society, or on building it up again, without having models
and patterns of approved utility before his eyes."
A sound
political system evolved gradually and inexplicably in response to historical
circumstance. Conservatives admired the English Constitution because it gave
expression to the unwritten and fundamental laws that bind people into a
nation. It was not a product of abstract thought: no assembly had
convened to fashion it. Because it had grown imperceptibly out of the
historical experiences and needs of the English people, it was durable and
effective. Conservatives thought of society as a living organism held
together by centuries old bonds, not a mechanical arrangement of disconnected
units. Alone a person would be selfish, unreliable and frail; it was only as
a member of a social group that one acquired the ways of cooperation and the
manners of civilization. Individualism overturned the very bases of human
society; it shattered traditional ties that made people care for each other
and the community; it destroyed obedience to law and authority and fragmented
society into disconnected parts: isolated, self-seeking atoms devoid of
any spiritual or civic purpose.
Conservatives
denounced Locke's social contract theory as a threat to established
monarchical power. The government did not derive authority from the consent
of the governed. Conservatives also rejected the philosophy of natural
rights. Rights were not universal abstractions which preceded an individual's
entrance into society. The state determined what rights and privileges its
people might possess. There were no 'rights of man', only rights of the
English, the French and so forth, as determined by the particular state.
Conservatives viewed 'political equality' as another of those pernicious
abstractions that contradicted all historical experience. Society was
naturally hierarchical. Some men by virtue of their intelligence, education,
wealth and birth were best qualified to rule. The revolutionaries had
deprived society of its most effective leaders by uprooting a traditional ruling elite which had learned its art
through long experience.
Liberalism: The Value of the
Individual
The decades
after 1815 saw a spectacular rise of the bourgeoisie. Talented and ambitious
bankers, merchants, professionals, and officeholders wanted to break the
stranglehold of the landed nobility, the traditional elite, on political
power and social prestige. The political philosophy of the bourgeoisie was
most commonly liberalism. Liberals wanted to carry out the promise of the
Enlightenment and the early phases of the French Revolution.
The
liberal's central concern was the enhancement of individual liberty. They
agreed with Immanuel Kant that all persons exist as ends in themselves and
not as an object to be used arbitrarily by others. Freed from the coercion of
government and church, and properly educated, a person could develop into a
good, productive and self-directed human being. Unfettered by ignorance and
tyranny, the mind could eradicate traditions and prejudices that had burdened
people for centuries and begin an age of free institutions and responsible
citizenship. Liberals supported the advancement of education, endorsed the
open mindedness of science; they encouraged open debate between opposing
viewpoints and tolerated dissent.
Holding that
the individual could handle his affairs better than any church or government
could, liberals attacked the state and other authorities that prevented
people from exercising their right of free choice, deprived them of their
privacy, interfered with the right of free expression or hindered their
development. John Stuart Mill said in On Liberty "...The only
purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a
civilized community against his will is to prevent harm to others.... Over
himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign."
To guard
against the absolute and arbitrary authority of rulers, liberals demanded
written constitutions that granted freedom of speech, of the press, and of
religion, freedom from arbitrary arrest and the protection of property
rights. To prevent the abuse of political authority, liberals called for a
freely elected legislature and the distribution of power among several
branches of government. Government derived its authority from the consent of
the governed, as given in free elections. The best government was the one
which governs least, which interferes as little as possible with the economic
activities of its citizens and does not involve itself in their private lives
or their beliefs.
Liberals
broke with an ancient civic tradition, derived from the Greek city-state,
which regarded the polis as a second family within which the individual could
develop politically, morally and intellectually. For liberals, the individual
was an independent unit whose needs took precedence over communal concerns.
They believed that self-interest did not fragment the community into
isolated, anti-social units; instead it worked to the advantage of both the
individual and the community. Free to fulfill his individual potential, the
individual would recognize that cooperation works to his own advantage.
Self-interest would thus be naturally tempered by reason and benevolence.
Alexis de Toqueville
and the Problem of Democracy
Liberals had
been dismayed by the radicalism of the Jacobins during the Revolution,
particularly when they had started to tamper with the economy. They also
feared the social disorder threatened by the masses of the poor. In the hands
of the lower classes, the natural rights philosophy was too easily translated
into the democratic creed that all people should share in political power: a
prospect that the bourgeois regarded with horror. Liberals opposed any
extension of political franchise beyond the middle class.
Few thinkers
in the first half of the nineteenth century grasped the growing significance
of the masses in politics as did Alexis de Toqueville
(1805-1859), the French political theorist and statesman. In the wake of the
French Revolution, Toqueville, an aristocrat by
birth but a liberal by temperament, recognized that the destruction of
aristocracy and the march toward democracy could not be curbed. In Democracy
in America (1835-1840), based on his travels in the United States, Toqueville with cool detachment and brilliance,
analyzed the nature, merits and weaknesses of American democratic society. In
contrast to France of the Old Regime, said Toqueville,
American society had no hereditary aristocracy with special privileges, and
the avenues of social advancement and political participation were open to
all.
Toqueville held
that democracy was more just than aristocratic government, and he predicted
that it would be the political system of the future, but he also recognized
its inherent dangers. In a democratic society people's passion to be equal
outweighs their desire for liberty. Spurred by the ideal of equality,
citizens in a democracy desire the honors and possessions that they think are
their due. They no longer accept the disparity in wealth and position as part
of the natural order. However, since people are not equal in ability, many
are frustrated and turn to the state to secure for them those possessions and
advantages they cannot obtain by themselves. They are willing to sacrifice
political liberty to improve their material well being. Consequently,
democracies face an ever-present danger in that people, craving to achieve
equality, will surrender their liberty to a central government that promises
to provide them with property and other advantages. Liberty would be lost to
the tyranny of the majority which seeks to impose its viewpoint on the
minority. To prevent democracy from degenerating into state despotism, Toqueville urged strengthening institutions of local
government, forming private associations over which the state had no control,
protecting the independence of the judiciary and preserving a free press.
Toqueville also
believed that democracy spawned a selfish individualism that could degenerate
into vulgar hedonism. Driven by an overriding concern for possessions and
profits, people would lose their taste for political participation and their
concern for the public good. If preoccupation with private concerns prevails
over a sense of public duty, liberty cannot long endure.
The task of
a democratic society is to temper extreme individualism and unrestrained
acquisitiveness by fostering public-spiritedness. Without direct
participation by civic-minded citizens concerned with the common good,
democracy faces a bleak future. Freedom depends less on laws than on
cultivating the sentiments and habits of citizenship.
The fear of
democracy among bourgeois liberals led them to set property requirements for
voting and office holding. They wanted political power to be concentrated in
the hands of a safe and reliable middle class. When the fever of revolution
spread to the masses, bourgeois liberals either withdrew or turned
counter-revolutionary. Even so, the essential ideals of democracy flowed from
liberalism. Eventually, democracy became a later stage in the evolution of
liberalism because the masses, their political power enhanced by the
Industrial Revolution, would press for greater social, political and economic
equality. The ideals of liberty and equality are by nature universal and inclusive, denying them to people on the basis of class,
race or gender cannot be convincingly defended. By the early twentieth
century, many European states had introduced universal manhood suffrage,
abandoned property requirements for office holding, and enacted laws to
improve conditions for workers.
However, the
fears of nineteenth-century liberals were not without foundation. In the twentieth
century, the participation of the common people in politics has indeed
threatened freedom. Impatient with parliamentary procedures and seduced by
appeals to passion and prejudices, the masses, particularly when troubled by
economic problems, have in some instances turned their support to demagogues
who promised swift and decisive action. The people have been willing to trade
freedom for authority, order, economic security and national power.
Liberal Economic Thought
In the last
part of the eighteenth century, as a revolution for liberty and equality
swept across France, the Industrial Revolution began to transform Great
Britain. In the nineteenth century, it spread to the United States and to the
European continent.
Rapid
industrialization caused hardships for the new class of industrial workers,
many of them recent arrivals from the countryside. Arduous and monotonous
factory labor was geared to the strict discipline of the clock, the machine
and the production schedule. Employment was never secure. Sick workers
received no pay and were often fired; aged workers suffered pay cuts or lost
their jobs. During business slumps, employers lowered wages with impunity,
and laid off workers had nowhere to turn for assistance. Because factory
owners often did not consider safety to be important, accidents were
frequent. Municipal authorities were unable to cope with the rapid pace of
urbanization and without adequate housing, sanitation or recreational facilities, the exploding urban centers were another source
of working-class misery. In pre-industrial Britain most people had lived in
small villages where their roots had been clear: relatives, friends and the
village church gave them a sense of belonging. The new industrial centers
separated people from nature and from their origins, shattering traditional
ways of life. The plight of the working class created a demand for reform,
but the British government, committed to laissez-faire economic principles
that militated against state involvement, was slow to act.
Adam Smith and The Wealth of Nations (1776)
The Wealth of Nations, written by Adam Smith, professor of moral
philosophy in Scotland, became the foundation of liberal economic theory.
Smith attacked the theory of mercantilism, which held that a state's wealth
was determined by the amount of gold and silver it possessed. To build its
reserves of precious metals, the state should promote domestic industries,
encourage exports, and discourage imports. Mercantilist theory called for
government regulation of the economy so that the state could compete for the
world's resources. Smith argued that the quantity and quality of its goods
and services measured the real basis of a country’s wealth, not its
storehouse of precious metals. Government intervention retards the economic
progress; it reduces the real value of the nation's land and labor. On the
other hand, when people pursue their own interests, when they seek to better
their own condition, they foster economic expansion, which benefits the whole
society. Left to its own devices, Smith maintained, the market mechanism
works ultimately for the benefit of all members of society, a view that
supported the Enlightenment's belief in progress.
"Every
individual is continually exerting himself to find out the most
advantageous employment for whatever capital he can command. It is his own advantage, indeed, and not that of society,
which he has in view. But the study of his own advantage, naturally or
necessarily, leads him to prefer that employment which is most advantageous
to the society.... By pursuing his own interest he frequently promotes that
of society more effectually than he intends to promote it. I have never
known much good done by those who affected to trade for the publick good." (Smith, The Wealth of Nations)
|
Smith
limited the state's authority to maintaining law and order, administering
justice, and defending the nation. He believed that competition was
self-regulating, as if an 'invisible hand' held greed in check and promoted
the general good. He did not intend to apologize for bourgeois self-interest.
He was critical of the manufacturers who, driven by greed, deceived and
oppressed the public. The free market functions best, he said, when business
people in pursuit of their own interests do not take unfair advantage of
others and do not neglect the common good. He did not view poverty as an
ineradicable law of nature. He believed that the working classes should have
a fair share of the wealth generated by their labor, and he argued that decent
wages increased the profitability of a business by encouraging hard work.
Nevertheless,
the principle of laissez faire- that government should not interfere
with the market was used by the bourgeoisie to justify its opposition to
humanitarian legislation intended to alleviate the misery of the factory
workers.
Thomas Malthus
Another
theorist favored by bourgeois liberals was Thomas R. Malthus (1766-1834), an
Anglican cleric and professor of history and political economy. In his Essay on the Principle of Population
(1798), Malthus asserted that the population grows at a much faster rate than
the food supply. This results in food shortages, irregular unemployment. lowered wages and high mortality. The poor's distress,
said Malthus, was not due to faulty political institutions or existing social
and property relations. Its true cause was the number of children they had.
"When
the wages of labour are hardly sufficient to
maintain two children, a man marries and has five or six. He of course
finds himself miserably distressed.... He accuses his parish.... He accuses
the avarice of the rich. He accuses the partial and unjust institutions of
society.... In searching for objects of accusation, he never adverts to the
quarter from which all his misfortunes originate. The last person he would
think of accusing is himself." (Malthus Principle of Population)
|
The state
cannot ameliorate the poor's misery, said Malthus: "the means of redress
are in their own hands, and in the hands of no other persons whatever."
This 'means of redress' would be lowering the birthrate through late
marriages and chastity, but Malthus believed that the poor lacked the
self-discipline to refrain from sexual activity. When they receive higher
wages, they have more children, thereby upsetting the population-resource
balance and bringing misery to themselves and others. This view of poverty as
an iron law of nature, which could not be undone by the good intentions of
the state or through philanthropy, buttressed supporters of laissez-faire and
eased the consciences of the propertied classes. Compassion for the poor was
simply a misplaced emotion; government reforms were doomed to fail, and
higher wages provided no relief. Malthus' theories also flew in the face of adherents
of human perfectibility and inevitable progress. Poverty, like disease, was
simply a natural phenomenon, one of nature's laws that could not be
eliminated. No wonder hiis contemporaries called
economics 'the dismal science'.
Early
nineteenth century liberals saw poverty and suffering as part of the natural
order and beyond government's scope. They feared that state intervention in
the economy to redress social ills disrupted the free market, threatening
personal liberty, and hindering social well-being. Government interference,
liberals also argued, discouraged the poor from finding work, thereby
promoting idleness. According to liberal political economy, unemployment and
poverty stemmed from individual failings.
Malthus
departed from the general view of the philosophes,
which saw natural law as beneficent and a model for human law. To the
political economist, natural law entailed human suffering and provided no
relief. In the last part of the nineteenth century liberals modified their
adherence to strict laissez-faire, accepting the principle that the
state had some responsibility to protect the poor against the worst abuses of
rapid industrialization.
Radicalism and Democracy: The
Expansion of Liberalism
In the early
nineteenth century, democratic ideals were advance by thinkers and activists
called radicals. Inspired by the Jacobin stage of the French Revolution and
by the democratic principles expressed in Rousseau's Social Contract,
early nineteenth century French radicals championed popular sovereignty: rule
by the people. In contrast to liberals who were generally fearful and
disdainful of the masses, French radicals trusted the common person.
Advocating universal manhood suffrage and a republic, radicalism gained the
support of many French workers and the lower bourgeois in the 1830's and
1840's.
British
radicals, like their liberal cousins, inherited the Enlightenment's
confidence in reason and its belief in the essential goodness of the individual.
In the first half of the nineteenth century, radicals sought parliamentary
reforms because some heavily populated districts were barely represented in
Parliament, while lightly populated districts were over represented. They
demanded payment for members of Parliament to permit the non-wealthy to hold
office; they sought universal manhood suffrage to give the masses
representation in Parliament; and they insisted on the secret ballot to
prevent intimidation of voters. Radicals attacked the hereditary aristocracy
and fought corruption.
English
radicalism embodied the desires of parliamentary reformers for broader
political representation and the hopes of the laboring poor for a better
life. Two important theorists of the movement were Thomas Paine and Jeremy
Bent ham.
Thomas Paine responded to Burke's Reflections
on the French Revolution with the Rights
of Man (1791). In it he denounced reverence for tradition, defended the
principle of natural rights and praised as progress the destruction of the
Old Regime. The only legitimate government, he claimed, was representative
democracy, in which the right of all men to participate was assured. Paine
believed that democratic governments would be less inclined than hereditary
ones to wage war and more concerned with the welfare of the common person.
Paine supported revolution as the means of creating a truly just society, one
that took reason and nature as its guide.
Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) rejected the doctrine of natural rights as
an abstraction that had no basis in reality. He regarded the French
Revolution as an absurd attempt to reconstruct society according to
principles as misguided as those that had supported the Old Regime. Bentham's
importance to the English radical tradition derives from the principle of
utility, which he offered as a guide to reformers. The central fact of human
existence, said Bentham, is that human beings seek to gratify their desires,
that they prefer pleasure to pain, and that pleasure is intrinsically good
and pain bad. In Bentham's view, human beings are motivated solely by
self-interest, which they define in terms of pleasure and pain. Consequently,
any political, economic, judicial or social institution and any legislation
should be judged according to a simple standard: does it bring the greatest
happiness to the greatest number? If not, it should be swept away.
Bentham
believed that he had found an objective and scientific approach to the study
and reform of society. By focusing on the need for change and improvement on
every level of society and by urging careful and objective analysis of social
issues, Bentham and his followers, called philosophical radicals, contributed
substantially to the shaping of the English reform tradition. He contended
that the principle of utility, to act always for the greatest good of the
greatest number of people, permits the reforming of society in accordance
with people's true nature and needs. It does not impose unrealistic standards
on men and women but accepts people as they are. Utilitarianism, he declared,
bases institutions and laws on an objective study of human nature, on
enlightened self-interest, rather than on unsubstantiated religious beliefs,
unreliable traditions, and mistaken philosophical abstractions.
Bentham's
utilitarianism led him to press for social and political reforms. The
aristocratic ruling elite, he said, were not interested in producing the
greatest happiness for the greatest number but in furthering their own narrow
interests. Only if the rulers came from the broad masses of people would
government be amenable to reforms bases on the greatest happiness principle.
He supported extension of suffrage and a secret ballot and attacked political
corruption. In contrast to laissez-faire liberals, Benthamites
argued for legislation to protect women and children in the factories-, they
also sought to improve sanitation in the cities and to reform the prison
system.
Early
Socialism: New Possibilities for Society
A new group
of social theorists proposed radically different methods for dealing with the
problems created by industrialization. Socialists argued that the
liberals' concern for individual freedom and the radicals' demand for
extension of suffrage had little impact on the poverty, oppression and gross
inequality of wealth that plagued modern society. Asserting that the
liberals' doctrine of individualism degenerated into selfish egoism, which
harmed community life, socialists called for the creation of a new society
based on cooperation rather than competition. Reflecting the spirit of the
enlightenment and the French Revolution, socialists, like liberals, denounced
the status quo for perpetuating injustice and held that people could create a
better world. Like liberals, too, they placed the highest value on the rational
analysis of society and transforming society in accordance with
scientifically valid premises, whose truth rational people could comprehend.
Socialists believed that they had discerned a pattern in human society,
which, if properly understood and acted upon, would lead men and women to an
earthly salvation. Thus, socialists were romantics, for they dreamed of a
new social order, a future utopia, where each individual could find happiness
and self-fulfillment.
An early
expression of socialist thinking emerged during the French Revolution, when Gracchus Babeuf (1760-1797), an ardent supporter of the sans-culottes, the
laboring poor, sought to end the division of society into exploiter and
exploited by abolishing private property. At his trial he said,
"It is the destiny
of the wretched of the earth to rule it; theirs is the right to talk as
masters to the governments that neglect them.... In a truly just social
order there are neither rich nor poor. The rich, who refuse to give up
their superfluous wealth for the benefit of the poor, are enemies of the
people."
|
Early nineteenth century
socialists regarded
the organization of society as inept and unjust. They denounced as hollow and
hypocritical the liberals' preoccupation with liberty and equality, arguing
that to the lower classes devastated by poverty these ideals were merely
formal principles: they protected the person and property of the wealthy
while the majority were enmired
in poverty and helplessness. Denying that human beings fared best as
competing individuals, socialists contended that people achieved more
happiness for themselves and for others as members of a cooperative
community, which lived, worked and planned together for the common good.
Some socialists proposed communes or model factory towns as places to realize
socialist ideals. The most important early nineteenth century socialist
thinkers- Saint-Simon, Fourier and Owen espoused a new social and economic
system in which production and distribution of goods would be planned for the
general good of society. Their thought influenced Karl Marx and Friedrich
Engels, who in the second half of the nineteenth century,
became the most influential formulators and propagators of socialism.
Henri
Comte de Saint Simon (1760-1825) was descended from a distinguished French
aristocratic family, but he renounced his title during the French Revolution
and enthusiastically preached the opportunity for a new society. He argued
that just as Christianity had provided social unity and stability during the
Middle Ages, scientific knowledge would bind the society of his time. The
scientists, engineers, industrialists, bankers, artists, and writers would
replace the unproductive classes- clergy, aristocracy and idle rich- as the
new social elite. In the new industrial age, the control of society must pass
to the 'indistriels'- productive people who
would harness technology for the betterment of humanity and eliminate the
causes of social conflict.
Like the philosophes, Saint-Simon valued science, had confidence
in the power of reason to improve society, and believed in the certainty of
progress according to laws of social development. He believed that industrial
society constituted a new stage in history, that unchecked individualism was
detrimental to society, and creative and collective
planning was necessary to cope with social ills.
Another
early French socialist was Charles
Fourier (1772-1837). He believed that society conflicted with the natural needs of human
beings and that this tension was responsible for human misery. Only the
reorganization of society so that it would fulfill people's desires for
pleasure and satisfaction would end that misery. Fourier sought to create
small communities to allow men and women to enjoy life's simple pleasures.
These communities or about 1,600 people, called phalansteries,
would be organized according to the unchanging needs of human nature. In phalansteries, no force would coerce or thwart
innocent human lives. Holding that human beings have been degraded by
dehumanizing manual labor, Fourier sought to make work emotionally
satisfying. All people would work at tasks that interested them and would
produce things that brought them and others pleasure; consequently, work
would look like play. In the phalansteries,
money and goods would not be equally distributed; those with special skills
and responsibilities would be compensated accordingly. This system of rewards
accorded with nature, said Fourier, because people have a natural desire to
be rewarded. Fourier supported female equality and not simply in political
terms. He believed the institution of marriage distorted the natures of both
men and women because monogamy restricted their sexual needs; human nature
required variety. Fourier also hoped that the family unit would eventually
disappear, believing that women had to devote all their time and strength to
household and children. The community itself would care for the children.
In the
United States during the 1840's at least twenty nine communities were founded
on Fourier's principles, but none lasted for longer than five or six years.
In 1799 Robert Owen (1771-1858) became the part owner and manager of the New
Lanark cotton mills in Scotland. He was distressed by the widespread
mistreatment of his workers and resolved to improve the lives of his
employees and do so while not destroying profits. He raised wages, upgraded
working conditions, refused to hire children under ten, and provided workers
with neat homes, food, clothing, all at reasonable prices. He set up schools
for children and for adults. In every way he demonstrated his belief that
happier, healthier workers produced more than less fortunate ones.
He held that
the environment was the principal shaper of character, that
the ignorance, alcoholism and crime of the poor derived from bad living
conditions. Public education and factory reform would make better citizens
off the poor. When Parliament balked at reforms, Owen even encouraged the creation
of a grand national trade union of all the workers in England. In the
earliest days on industrialization, this dream seemed an impossible one. He
established a model community at New Harmony, Indiana, but it was
short-lived.
|